1 Introduction

Within semantics and pragmatics, where the aim is to understand the inferences drawn from (uses of) sentences, this paper zooms in on a particular class of inferences: those drawn from sentences with a plural subject (such as Alice and Bob) about how each member of the subject participates in the predicate of the sentence (Bartsch 1973; Scha 1981; Link 1983; Roberts 1987); see Winter & Scha (2015); Nouwen (2015); de Vries (2017); Champollion (2019; 2020) for recent overviews.

(1) conveys that Alice and Bob each smiled. Smile is therefore distributive: inferred to be individually true of (to distribute down to) each member of the plural subject. (Distributivity applies to all sorts of plurals, but I focus on conjoined names for clarity.)

(1) Alice and Bob smiled. (distributive)
  a. ✓Distributive: Alice smiled, Bob smiled.
  b. ✗Nondistributive: Alice and Bob smiled jointly but not individually.

In contrast, (2) does not convey that each person met – at least, not unless one imagines some sort of implicit object. Instead, meet is true of Alice and Bob together, not each one individually: nondistributive.1

(2) Alice and Bob met. (nondistributive)
  a. ✗Distributive: Alice met, Bob met.
  b. ✓Nondistributive: Alice and Bob met jointly but not individually.

Whereas smile is distributive and meet is nondistributive, (3) can be interpreted in both ways: it can describe a situation in which Alice and Bob each opened the door (distributive); or a situation in which Alice and Bob did not technically each open the door, because they did so by working together (nondistributive).

(3) Alice and Bob opened {the/a} door. (can be understood both ways)
  a. ✓Distributive: Alice opened {the/a} door, Bob opened {the/a} door.
  b. ✓Nondistributive: Alice and Bob opened {the/a} door jointly but not individually.

With an indefinite object (3), a predicate built from a transitive verb has the potential for covariation (Dotlačil 2010) – for the indefinite to covary with each member of the subject, as when (3) is interpreted to involve two different doors. In general, when a predicate can be interpreted as either distributive or nondistributive (3), and especially when its distributive interpretation would involve covariation, the nondistributive interpretation is favored even if both interpretations are available in principle (Brooks & Braine 1996; Frazier et al. 1999; Dotlačil 2010; Syrett & Musolino 2013; Dobrovie-Sorin et al. 2016).

This empirical picture raises two big questions, a formal semantics question which has been discussed widely, and a lexical semantics question which has largely remained open.

First, the widely discussed formal semantics question (Scha 1981; Link 1983; Dowty 1987; Roberts 1987; Landman 1989; Lasersohn 1995; Schwarzschild 1996; Winter 1997; Landman 2000; Winter 2002; Champollion 2010; de Vries 2015; Champollion 2016; 2017): How should sentences like (1)–(3) be represented formally? To what extent should the inferences drawn from these sentences manifest transparently in their semantic representation? In particular, how do we capture the two distinct interpretations available to (3) – in terms of a semantic ambiguity (Roberts 1987; Landman 1989; Lasersohn 1995; Champollion 2010), or in terms of an underspecified meaning compatible with multiple different situations (Schwarzschild 1996; Kratzer 2007)? If (3) is ambiguous, why are (1) and (2) unambiguous?

Second, the much less-discussed lexical semantics question: Which other predicates behave like smile, like meet, or like open the door – and why? Uncontroversially, the inferences drawn from these predicates are shaped by our knowledge about how events of smiling, meeting, and door-opening take place in the world (Dowty 1987; Roberts 1987; Winter 1997; 2000; Champollion 2010; de Vries 2015). Smile is distributive (1) because people have their own faces and thus cannot smile jointly without also doing so individually. Meet is nondistributive (2) because it describes an inherently social action that cannot be undertaken unilaterally. Open the door can be understood in both ways (3) because it can be carried out individually or jointly.

Prior work has illuminated various elements of the relation between lexical semantics and plural predication, including the interpretation of adjectives (Scontras & Goodman 2017; Glass 2018a), reciprocity (Kruitwagen et al. 2017; Poortman et al. 2018; Winter 2018), whether a predicate applied to a plural must apply to every single member of it (Yoon 1996), different types of non-distributive predicates (Corblin 2008; Kuhn 2020), interactions with negation (Löbner 2000; Križ 2016), and the distribution of the modifier all (Dowty 1987; Löbner 2000; Winter 2000; Brisson 2003). But there is still a need for a predictive theory of which predicates are interpreted as distributive and/or nondistributive and why, in view of lexical/world knowledge about the events that they describe.

There is an ongoing “dictionary versus encyclopedia” debate about what knowledge should be tied to particular lexical items versus one’s extralinguistic knowledge of the world (Fillmore 1969; Pustejovsky 1995; Harley & Noyer 1999; Peeters 2000; McNally 2005). The noncommittal term lexical/world knowledge is intended to sidestep that issue. Here, the aim is to systematize the knowledge relevant for distributivity, without deciding whether that knowledge is lexical or encyclopedic or both.

This paper takes on the lexical semantics question. §2 motivates a series of predictions about the behavior of various types of predicates, generalizing the intuitive analysis of predicates such as smile and open the door to a larger scale. To preview:

(4) Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry: Predicates built from many intransitive verbs (smile, laugh, arrive, die) are only distributive, whereas predicates built from many transitive verbs (open a door, eat a pizza) can be nondistributive.
(5) Mind Prediction: Because individuals have their own minds, predicates describing the subject’s mental processes (believe it, love a movie, meditate, see a photo, worry) are distributive.
(6) Causative Prediction: Because the nature of causation allows that multiple individuals’ contributions may be jointly sufficient but individually insufficient to cause a result, predicates built from causative verbs (describing an event where the subject causes the object to change, such as annoy a neighbor, break a vase, destroy a family, open a door) can be nondistributive as well as distributive.

§3 presents distributivity judgments from online annotators for over one thousand English predicates (intransitive verbs, and transitive verbs with corpus-motivated objects). For each verb, the features predicted to shape its distributivity potential are labeled using FrameNet (Baker et al. 1998), a lexical database that records inferentially relevant features of events described by verbs. §4 presents a statistical analysis of those annotations, finding evidence consistent with (4)–(6). The observed asymmetry between transitive and intransitive verbs (4) is explained using the Causative Prediction (6): many transitive verbs (even, I argue, those not strictly categorized as “causative”) describe events in which the subject affects (causes a change upon an object), so that the structure of causation gives them a nondistributive interpretation.

Turning to the formal semantics question, §5 reviews the literature to emphasize that any semantic representation of distributivity must be complemented by a predictive analysis, like the one offered here, of which predicates are interpreted in which ways and why.

Broadly (§6), this paper aims to explore distributivity at a large scale; and to show that distributivity is productively handled not just as a formal semantics topic, but as a lexical semantics one.

2 Predicting distributivity across the lexicon

This section motivates a series of predictions about the types of predicates that are interpreted as distributive (like smile), nondistributive (like meet), or in both ways (like open the/a door).

In general, most predicates can be interpreted as distributive, because most predicates – all the ones that make sense with an atomic subject – describe actions that can be carried out by a single individual (Alice smiled, Alice opened the door). The only exceptions are (i) reciprocal predicates like meet, which describe inherently multilateral actions; and (ii) predicates with definite objects describing actions that cannot be repeated on the same object (break the vase; the same vase generally cannot be broken repeatedly). Because most predicates can be interpreted as distributive, it is most informative to distinguish between the predicates that can only be distributive (smile), versus those that allow a nondistributive interpretation in addition to a distributive one (open the/a door).

I focus on the predictions (§2.1–§2.3) that are supported in the annotation study reported below (§3, §4), before sketching (§2.4) some other predictions that did not reach statistical significance there.

2.1 The Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry

Nearly forty years ago, Link (1983) observed that a predicate’s distributivity potential is related to its argument structure:

(7) The Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry: Predicates built from many intransitive verbs (smile, laugh, arrive, die) are only distributive, whereas predicates built from many transitive verbs (open a door, eat a pizza) can be nondistributive.

After observing that carry the piano (built from a transitive verb) can be both distributive and nondistributive, Link writes: “Common nouns and intransitive verbs like die, however, seem to admit only atoms in their extension. I call such predicates distributive” (Link 1983: 132). He reiterates (Link 1983: 141): “Most of the basic count nouns like child are taken as distributive, similarly IV [intransitive verb] phrases like die or see.”

Of course, there are counter-examples: love a movie is built from a transitive verb and is only distributive (presumably because people have their own emotional attitudes); meet is intransitive and nondistributive. But as a tendency, (7) is plausible. To use introspective evidence, all the intransitive verbs in (8) behave like smile in that if Alice and Bob carry out these actions, then they each do so (distributive).

(8) arrive, blush, die, disappear, faint, fall, laugh, meditate, pray, run, swim, walk, wink, …
  distributive, ✗nondistributive

In contrast, all of the predicates built from transitive verbs in (9) behave like open the/a door in that if Alice and Bob carry out these actions, they may do so jointly rather than individually (nondistributive). (The predicates in (9) can also be interpreted as distributive, with or without covariation depending on whether the action described by the verb can be repeated on the same object; but the important point is that they can be interpreted as nondistributive.)

(9) create a controversy, eat a pizza, score a point, send a letter, write a book, …
  (distributive), ✓nondistributive

Unlike the other predictions proposed below, (7) has no obvious theoretical motivation; if it is manifested, we face a deeper question of why it would be so. To preview, I suggest below that many transitive verbs describe events of causation, independently shown to favor nondistributivity.

2.2 The Mind Prediction

Love a movie is distributive because loving is a mental attitude, which people experience individually. The same reasoning should extend to other predicates describing the mental processes of an experiencer, such as perception, emotion, and thought. This intuition is inspired by Roberts (1987), who observes that predicates describing self-willed actions are inherently distributive:

“The fact that a particular lexical item is a group predicate or a distributive predicate doesn’t really need to be specified independently: it follows from the sense of the predicate itself. […] What is it to be a pop star or to walk or to die? The actions or states denoted by these verbs can generally only be performed or endured by an individual with a single will and consciousness. It is for this reason that we think of them as distributive.”—Roberts (1987): p. 124

In other words:

(10) Mind Prediction: Because individuals have their own minds, predicates describing the subject’s mental or emotional processes (believe it, hear a sound, love a movie, worry) are distributive.

2.3 The Causative Prediction

It is less obvious why open the/a door prefers to be nondistributive, or which other predicates should pattern with it.

My proposal is that open is a causative verb (Smith 1970; Fillmore 1970; Dowty 1979), describing an event in which the subject causes the object to change in openness. By definition, causatives describe events of causation. I argue that this truism predicts the distributivity potential of such predicates: as a general fact about causation, captured by any adequate analysis of it (Swanson 2012; Menzies 2014; Copley & Wolff 2014), it is possible for the actions of multiple individuals to be jointly-but-not-individually sufficient (Mackie 1965) to bring about a result.

Illustrating with the influential counterfactual analysis of causation from Hume (1748), revitalized by Lewis (1973) and synthesized with distributivity by Dowty (1987), a sentence such as Alice and Bob opened the door is analyzed to mean that a and b (Alice’s action and Bob’s action) cause a result d (the opening of the door). Perhaps a caused d and b caused d (distributive), meaning that Alice’s action caused the door to open, and Bob’s action caused the door to open too (11a). But perhaps Alice’s action and Bob’s action (a and b) were jointly but not individually sufficient to cause the door to open: if Alice or Bob had acted alone, the door would still not be open (11b). Because two events may be jointly but not individually sufficient to cause a result, we predict that when a causative is predicated of a plural subject, the sentence may be interpreted as nondistributive (in addition to a distributive interpretation, which depends on the repeatability of the action and the definteness of the object). Perhaps Alice unlocks the door, and Bob pushes it open, so that the door would not have opened but for Alice’s action and Bob’s action together.

(11) Alice and Bob opened {the/a} door.
  a. (✓Distributive: They each opened {the/a} door.)
  b. ✓Nondistributive: They opened {the/a} door jointly without each individually doing so.
    (Alice unlocks it, Bob pushes it open.)

To generalize, this discussion leads to a prediction:

(12) Causative Prediction: Because the nature of causation allows that multiple individuals’ contributions may be jointly sufficient but individually insufficient to cause a result, predicates built from causative verbs (describing an event where the subject causes the object to change, such as annoy a neighbor, break a vase, destroy a family, open a door) should allow a nondistributive interpretation (in addition, perhaps, to a distributive one).

2.4 Other predictions (which turned out not significant)

I turn to some other predictions which, while intuitively motivated, did not reach statistical significance in the annotation study (§3) reported below.

Smile is distributive because it describes a facial action which people can only carry out individually. The same reasoning should extend to other predicates describing the actions of an individual body, including actions of the face, voice, and self-propelled motion (Roberts 1987; de Vries 2015). Thus:

(13) Body Prediction: Because individuals have their own bodies, predicates describing the actions of an individual body (chew, faint, jump, laugh, sing, smile, shrug, walk) are distributive.

Some predicates describe an event where an object, called an incremental theme (Dowty 1991), is affected in tandem with the progress of the event of affecting it (Tenny 1987; Krifka 1992). Eat a pizza describes an event that is half over when a pizza is half-eaten, and fully over when it is fully eaten. Such events are not necessarily causative; the progress of a read a book event maps incrementally to the parts of the book, but does not describe a caused change therein (Rappaport Hovav 2008).

If two people eat a pizza, perhaps they each eat one (distributive), or perhaps they each eat a different portion of a single pizza, adding up to a whole pizza between them (nondistributive). Informally, it is always possible for multiple individuals to each carry out the event described by the verb on a different portion of an incremental object, only jointly adding up to the whole. To generalize:2

(14) Incremental Prediction: Because individuals may each affect a different portion of an incremental object, only jointly affecting the whole, predicates with incremental objects (build a house, eat a pizza, paint a wall, read the book, write a letter) are predicted to allow a nondistributive interpretation (in addition, perhaps, to a distributive one).

(15) can be understood in both ways (distributive and nondistributive), presumably because buying is a commercial transaction that can involve both individuals and larger parties.

(15) Alice and Bob bought a car. (can be understood both ways)
  a. ✓Distributive: Alice bought a car, Bob bought a car.
  b. ✓Nondistributive: Alice and Bob bought a car jointly but not individually.

The modern legal system allows property and commercial transactions to be shared as well as individualized. Thus:

(16) Commercial Prediction: Because money and property can be possessed collectively, predicates describing commercial transactions (buy/sell a car, lease/rent a room, pay a bill, owe a debt, donate a library, own a boat) are predicted to allow a nondistributive interpretation (in addition to a distributive one).

Intuitively, meet is nondistributive because it describes an inherently multilateral action which individuals cannot carry out alone. If an action requires multiple participants, then an individual person (Alice) cannot carry out that action alone (Carlson 1998; Siloni 2012). Therefore, predicates describing such actions cannot be distributive, but can only be nondistributive.3 To generalize:

(17) Multilateral Prediction: Because individuals cannot carry out inherently multilateral actions alone, predicates describing such actions (coexist, collaborate, cooperate, meet, share a pizza, tango) are predicted to be nondistributive.

Note that (17) is the only prediction about when nondistributivity is required; all the others predict when it is allowed.

2.5 Section summary

For certain predicates, one can identify an intuitive explanation for how they are understood (as distributive, nondistributive, or in both ways) when applied to a plural subject, based on the real-world event described by the predicate. This section has expanded such intuitive explanations into a series of predictions about the distributivity potential of various classes of predicates.

3 Distributivity annotations

To test these predictions, this section presents a dataset of 1020 predicates (intransitive verbs, and transitive verbs with corpus-motivated objects), annotated for distributivity using Amazon’s Mechanical Turk service.

3.1 Study design

Annotators encountered past-tense predicates applied to two conjoined human names, and answered questions such as (18)–(19) – thus annotating the predicate as either distributive (“technically each PRED”) or nondistributive (“jointly PRED without technically each doing so”).

(18) Nora and Ralph walked.
  From this sentence, one most likely infers that Nora and Ralph
 
(19) Kendall and Taylor reduced a risk.
  From this sentence, one most likely infers that Kendall and Taylor
 

For each predicate, the FrameNet database is used to label features of the event predicted (§2) to shape its distributivity potential.

The questions (18)–(19) elicit a binary judgment about whether to interpret the predicate as distributive (each) or nondistributive (jointly). For predicates where only one interpretation makes sense (walk, smile), annotators are expected to choose the only sensible answer. For predicates where both interpretations make sense in principle (reduce a risk, open a door), annotators are expected to choose either answer, but with a bias towards the nondistributive interpretation in light of the finding (Brooks & Braine 1996; Frazier et al. 1999; Dotlačil 2010; Syrett & Musolino 2013; Dobrovie-Sorin et al. 2016) that nondistributive interpretations are preferred when they are available. Thus, predicates that only make sense as distributive (smile) should be annotated as distributive; predicates that only make sense as nondistributive (meet; by far the smallest class) should be annotated as nondistributive; and predicates that can receive both interpretations (open a door) should tend to be annotated as nondistributive. Of course, the task is rather abstruse and annotators may interpret it in idiosyncratic ways, so we should realistically expect these predictions to manifest as tendencies rather than absolutes.

While (18)–(19) elicit a single binary judgment about how annotators actually interpret the sentence, prior work (Glass 2018b) asked two hypothetical questions, using a five-point Likert scale, about how annotators could interpret it: (a) “Does it follow that Nora and Ralph each walked?” and (b) “Could it be that Nora and Ralph didn’t technically each walk, because they did so together?” The current formulation was chosen because it is simpler (asking about one’s actual interpretation rather than hypothetical ones, using a binary scale rather than a Likert scale for what is really a binary distinction); it eliminates the confusing redundancy of asking two inversely related questions; and it avoids the notoriously polysemous word together, which can evoke both nondistributivity and socio-spatial coordination (Moltmann 2004). But, as expected, the 2018 data are strongly correlated with the new data reported here,4 meaning that both formats probe the same phenomenon.

3.2 Choosing corpus-motivated verbs

The verbs to be annotated were chosen using a corpus of comments from Reddit, a United States-based online discussion platform. Reddit is organized into sub-communities with more or less specialized interests (r/bicycling, r/movies); here, comments were taken only from r/AskReddit, one of the largest communities, dedicated to general-interest topics (recently popular: What is something about yourself that sounds totally made up but is 100% real?, and: People who shoved their school papers in their backpack with no binder/folder etc, where are you now?). Reddit is a massive, freely available dataset of contemporary English, using fairly standard orthography but with a register close to that of spoken English (Herring et al. 2013).

The AskReddit comments from January 2014 were downloaded from the PushShift repository5 and processed to remove all information about individual users, discussion thread structure, and upvotes/downvotes, as well as hyperlinks and comments by self-identified bots. In total, the comments comprise 110 million words.

Next, the comments were run through SpaCy (Honnibal & Johnson 2015), a natural language processing pipeline which tokenizes sentences, lemmatizes words, tags parts-of-speech, and parses the syntactic dependencies of each sentence. I counted all occurrences of each part-of-speech-tagged verb lemma in the data, and kept the verbs (excluding crude ones) with a per-million-word frequency of 2 or more. (Some of the least-frequent verbs in the data, with a per-million-word frequency of 2, include assist, await, bolt, and chuck; the most-frequent include get, make, say, want, and know, each with a per-million-word frequency of over 2000).

To create sentences such as (18)–(19) to be annotated, each verb also has to be classified as transitive (in which case it is given an object, using a process described below), or intransitive. Although many verbs can appear in both transitive and intransitive argument structures (I ate lunch; I ate; see, e.g., Levin 1993), this dataset annotates each verb only once, as either transitive or intransitive. Using the dependency parse from SpaCy, I computed the percent of the time that the verb appeared with a “dobj” (direct object) dependency, as a fraction of its overall occurrences. As a general rule, verbs were classified as transitive if they have a direct object more than 30% of the time, intransitive otherwise.6

3.3 Choosing corpus-motivated objects for transitive verbs

To create sentences to be annotated as in (19), each transitive verb must be given an object. The object of a transitive verb – both its grammatical properties and its referent – plays an important role in shaping the distributivity potential of a full predicate.

Grammatically, it matters whether the object is singular or plural. A predicate with a plural object can always be interpreted as nondistributive (“cumulative”; Scha 1981): if two people open two doors or see two photos, perhaps they do so by each opening/seeing one, adding up to two doors/photos between them (Krifka 1992; Champollion 2010). Singular objects were used to avoid that confound.

As previewed above (§1), a predicate’s potential for distributivity also depends on whether the object is definite or indefinite, which in turn interacts with whether the action described by the verb can be repeated on the same object (Champollion 2020).

(20) Alice and Bob opened {the/a} door.
  a. ✓Distributive: They each opened {the same, a different} door.
  b. ✓Nondistributive: They opened {the/a} (single) door jointly without each individually doing so.
(21) Alice and Bob broke {the, a} vase.
  a. {???/✓} Distributive: They each broke {??the same, a different} vase.
  b. ✓Nondistributive: They broke {the/a} (single) vase jointly without each individually doing so.

Because the same door can be opened more than once, (20) allows both interpretations regardless of whether its object is indefinite or definite. But because the same vase normally cannot be broken more than once, an indefinite object allows break a vase (21) to have a (covarying) distributive interpretation which is unavailable with a definite object. Thus, indefinite objects were used to abstract away from whether the action described by the verb can be repeated on the same object.

A predicate’s distributivity potential is also affected by the referent of its object. Open an eye is distributive, based on the knowledge that people have their own eyes. Open a book and open a vault can both go both ways, but may differ because it is easier to open books than vaults.

For this study, it is important to choose objects for verbs using a method that systematically controls for these issues. Particularly if the focus is verbs, we do not want the choice of object to confound the data. But we cannot give every verb the same object (open a door vs. #eat a door); and a generic object such as thing would be unnatural. Instead, the AskReddit corpus data were used to find, for each transitive verb, a list of its most-frequent lemmatized direct objects according to SpaCy’s dependency parse. (The list automatically excludes pronouns; demonstratives such as this; wh-words such as who and whatever; quantifiers such as anyone; partitives such as piece and lot; the highly bleached words other, way, and thing; and all vulgar words). By default, each transitive verb was given its most common lemmatized object, as a singular indefinite. I then went through by hand and identified any objects that did not make sense as a singular indefinite (mass nouns such as water, intensifiers such as hell, relational nouns such as end). In such cases, one of the next-most-common objects was chosen; for reduce, the object risk was chosen, because the more-common objects (amount, chance, number) would need further context to make sense.

(22) Most common lemmatized objects for the verb reduce, and their counts. amount(64), chance(48), number(41), risk(37), cost(32), rate(29), stress(19), level(15), price(13), pain(12)

The noun person was the most-common object for so many verbs that the next-most-common object, if it made sense as a singular indefinite, was chosen for balance.

This process yields objects that are naturalistically motivated, minimally shaped by researcher bias, and sensible as singular indefinites.

3.4 Labeling predicate features with FrameNet

Each predicate must also be labeled for the features predicted (§2) to shape its potential for distributivity. Of course, if the researcher labeled these features, the study might be vulnerable to confirmation bias – the researcher might choose labels consistent with their own beliefs about the predicate’s potential for distributivity, and then circularly use these labels to predict distributivity.

Therefore, labels were chosen in an automatic manner using the FrameNet database7 (Baker et al. 1998), which is built upon the theory of Frame Semantics from Fillmore (1976). Frame Semantics brings together the idea of thematic roles (the roles played by each argument of a verb in the event that it describes; Gruber 1965) with the idea that humans understand language using rich background knowledge – called frames, scripts, or schemas (Schank & Abelson 1977) – about stereotypical events.

FrameNet is a machine-readable database of such frames, built by semanticists and lexicographers. The lexical unit walk.v evokes the SELF-MOTION frame:

(23) SELF-MOTION: “The Self-Mover, a living being, moves under its own direction along a Path. Alternatively or in addition to Path, an Area, Direction, Source, or Goal for the movement may be mentioned.”

Each underlined word constitutes a Frame Element, to which each argument of the verb walk can be mapped. Reduce.v evokes the CAUSE-CHANGE-OF-POSITION-ON-A-SCALE frame:

(24) CAUSE-CHANGE-POSITION-ON-A-SCALE: “An Agent or a Cause affects the position of an Item on some scale (the Attribute) to change it from an initial value (Value1) to an end value (Value2). The direction of the change (Path) can be encoded as well as the magnitude of the change (Difference).”

Frames are related to other frames through various Frame-Frame relations. The SELF-MOTION frame “inherits” (is a more specific instance of) the MOTION frame. The CAUSE-CHANGE-POSITION-ON-A-SCALE frame (also evoked by related verbs such as add, double, and raise) serves as the “causative-of” the CHANGE-POSITION-ON-A-SCALE frame (which, in turn, is the “inchoative-of” the CAUSE-CHANGE-POSITION-ON-A-SCALE frame).

FrameNet was used – specifically, the version integrated into the Natural Language Toolkit (NLTK; Loper & Bird 2002) by Schneider & Wooters (2017) – to label predicates for the features predicted (§2) to shape their distributivity potential.

A predicate was labeled as a “mind” predicate if it evokes or inherits the frames EXPERIENCER-FOCUS (for verbs with experiencer subjects, such as love); PERCEPTION, EMOTIONS-OF-MENTAL-ACTIVITY, COGITATION, AWARENESS, MEMORY, and MENTAL-ACTIVITY; and/or if it requires a COGNIZER among its core Frame Elements. Because the prediction is about the subjects of mind verbs rather than their objects, verbs were excluded from this classification if they evoke the EXPERIENCER-OBJECT frame, describing the mental experience of the syntactic object (astonish; Grafmiller 2013) rather than the subject. In total, 127 predicates were labeled as “mind” predicates (112 transitives, 15 intransitives), including:

(25) admire a person, believe a story, care, crave a cigarette, dread a class, dislike a movie, feel a pain, grieve, hear a story, find a job, expect a tip, imagine a scenario, envy a friend, listen, perceive a threat, pity a fool, …

A predicate was labeled as “causative” if it involves a transitive verb (because causatives, as defined here, describe events in which a subject causes a change upon an object) and evokes or inherits the frames EXPERIENCER-OBJ (for “psych” verbs such as annoy, describing events in which a stimulus subject causes an emotion in an experiencer object); CAUSATION, or KILLING; if it evokes or inherits any frame with the CAUSE- prefix; if is related to any other frame through the “causative-of” frame relation; or if it requires a CAUSE among its core Frame Elements. In total, 314 predicates were labeled as causative (all transitive), including:

(26) activate a card, annoy a friend, arrest a person, baffle a doctor, bake a cake, butcher an animal, cast a spell, chill a drink, calm a child, develop a skill, dissolve a plastic, discourage a child, fry a chicken, melt a cheese, plant a seed, reduce a risk, rip a shirt, …

Any predicate was excluded from the study if its verb is absent from FrameNet (which has some odd gaps; blush, dream, edit, greet, and relax are absent). Even among the predicates that appear in FrameNet, quite a few of them do not receive any of the labels just described; for example, refuse an offer is labeled as neither “mind” nor “causative” nor any other label.8

Predicates were labeled before gathering any distributivity annotations, and the data to be annotated were pre-registered through the Open Science Framework (https://osf.io/ena5r/).

3.5 Data collection

In total, 1020 predicates were assembled, 161 intransitive verbs and 859 transitive verbs with objects, all labeled using FrameNet for the features predicted to shape their distributivity potential. These 1020 predicates were randomly split into 20 lists of about 50 predicates each.9 Each list of about 50 predicates was used to generate an annotation survey on the Qualtrics platform (using the “Loop and Merge” function to iterate over a list of predicates). Each predicate, in the past tense, was combined with a random conjunction of two names and placed in a question modeled after (18)–(19).

Using Amazon’s Mechanical Turk, 215 annotators were recruited10 with a goal of collecting (at least) nine annotations for each of the twenty lists of ~50 predicates. Annotators using United States I.P. addresses were paid $3.00 for what amounted to between seven and fifteen minutes of work. Two hundred and one (201) annotators were included in the analysis; fourteen were excluded because they either did not complete the study or they said, after being advised that they would be paid regardless of their answer, that their native language was not English.

Table 1 shows an excerpt of the data for the first three annotators. Subj1 rated the predicate boot a computer as distributive (“each booted a computer”); this predicate was also labeled as causative by the FrameNet procedure described above.

Table 1

For the first three annotators, this table shows their (distributive, nondistributive) annotations for some predicates that they encountered, as well as the features of the predicate (hypothesized to predict distributivity) labeled using FrameNet.

ID pred annotation labeled features
Subj1 booted a computer distributive causative
Subj1 failed a test distributive
Subj1 negotiated a price nondistributive
(…) (…) (…) (…)
Subj2 cared distributive mind
Subj2 dissolved a plastic nondistributive causative
Subj2 hurried distributive body
(…) (…) (…) (…)
Subj3 crashed a car nondistributive causative
Subj3 fell distributive
Subj3 imagined a scenario distributive mind

Figure 1 records a histogram of the percentage of distributive annotations for all 1020 predicates; Figure 2 shows examples of some predicates along with the percent of distributive annotations thereof; for example, nine of the ten annotations for admired a person rate it as distributive (consistent with the Mind Prediction).

Figure 1
Figure 1

Histogram of the percentage of distributive annotations.

Figure 2
Figure 2

Percentage of distributive annotations gathered for some example predicates.

4 Testing predictions about predicates’ distributivity potential

The next step is to use the annotations (§3) to test predictions (§2) about the distributivity potential of different types of predicates.

4.1 Statistical analysis

Data were analyzed with mixed-effects logistic regression models in R (the glmer function; Bates et al. 2015; R Core Team 2012, using the bobyqa optimizer of Powell 2009 to help them converge). A logistic regression predicts a binary dependent variable (here, an annotation of either distributive or nondistributive) as a function of one or more continuous or categorical independent variables. A mixed-effects model (Winter 2013) uses random effects to factor out systematic differences – between individual annotators or items – unrelated to the hypothesis being tested.

A series of models was built, using every hypothesized independent variable (§2) as well as subsets and combinations (additions and interactions) thereof. Models used random intercepts for each predicate and tried both random intercepts and random slopes for each annotator (Barr et al. 2013). Models were then compared using Analysis of Variation (anova), which rewards models for a balance of parsimony and data coverage. According to the anova, the best (most parsimonious and explanatory) model uses random intercepts for each predicate, random slopes and random intercepts for each annotator, and predicts the binary annotation outcome (distributive or nondistributive) from the independent variables of transitive, causative, and mind (each coded as a binary yes/no factor):

(27) glmer(annotation ~ transitive + caus + mind + (transitive | SubjId) + (mind | SubjId) + (caus | SubjId) + (1 | pred), data=d, family=binomial)

The independent variables in (27) remained significant across all models.

Table 2 illustrates the effect sizes, standard errors, and p values for each independent variable, and presents the model’s predicted probability (calculated using plogis) of each type of predicate being annotated as distributive.

Table 2

Statistical model.

ESTIMATE P(DIST) STD ERROR Z PR(>|Z|)
(Intercept=intrans) 1.29 78% 0.13 10.23 <0.001***
transitive –1.22 52% 0.13 –8.85 <0.001***
mind 0.52 86% 0.12 4.51 <0.001***
causative (& transitive) –0.26 45% 0.08 –3.28 <0.01**

Table 3 illustrates the extent to which these independent variables overlap with one another. For example, all causatives as defined here inherently involve transitive verbs; 37% of transitive verbs (314 of 859) are labeled as causative. But while these independent variables overlap, a Variance Inflation Factor test shows that they are not too collinear.11

Table 3

Number of predicates in each category, and overlap between the categories. Percentages are calculated using the count data in each cell as the numerator, and the column total (the bottom cell of each column) as the denominator.

TRANS INTRANS MIND CAUSATIVE OVERALL
trans 859 (100%) 0 (0%) 112 (88%) 314 (100%) 859 (84%)
intrans 0 (0%) 161 (100%) 15 (12%) 0 (0%) 161 (16%)
mind 112 (13%) 15 (9%) 127 (100%) 11 (3%) 127 (12%)
causative 314 (37%) 0 (0%) 11 (9%) 314 (100%) 314 (30%)
total 859 161 127 314 1020

The statistical model (27) (Table 2) shows evidence consistent with certain predictions about the distributivity potential of various predicates (§2).

4.2 Evidence consistent with the Causative Prediction

Causatives were predicted (28) (repeated from above) to allow a nondistributive interpretation.

(28) Causative Prediction: Because the nature of causation allows that multiple individuals’ contributions may be jointly sufficient but individually insufficient to cause a result, predicates built from causative verbs (describing an event where the subject causes the object to change, such as annoy a neighbor, break a vase, destroy a family, open a door) should allow a nondistributive interpretation (in addition, perhaps, to a distributive one).

This prediction is indeed manifested statistically (27). Figure 3 compares the average percentage of distributive annotations for causative predicates versus predicates built from other, non-causative transitive verbs. (All causatives are transitive, and the model finds a striking effect of transitivity to be explored below, so it is most illuminating to compare causatives to other transitives rather than to all verbs). A regular transitive verb has about a 52% chance of being annotated as distributive, while a causative transitive has about a 45% chance.

Figure 3
Figure 3

Average percentage of distributive annotations for transitive non-causative versus transitive causative verbs.

Causation is known to be grammatically and inferentially important (Smith 1970; Fillmore 1970; Dowty 1979; Levin 1993; Levin & Rappaport Hovav 1994; Rappaport Hovav & Levin 2010). Causative verbs are grammatically unique in that they are the only ones to participate in the causative-inchoative alternation of Smith (1970) (I opened the door/the door opened). They are inferentially unique in that they entail a change of state in their object/patient argument, and don’t specify exactly how the agent acted to bring it about. This paper identifies one more inferential consequence of causation: when applied to a plural subject, causative predicates systematically favor a nondistributive interpretation.

4.3 Evidence consistent with the Mind Prediction

Predicates describing mental actions were predicted (29) (repeated from above) to be distributive.

(29) Mind Prediction: Because individuals have their own minds, predicates describing the subject’s mental processes (believe it, love a movie, meditate, see a photo, worry) are distributive.

This prediction is indeed manifested (Figure 4). Across both transitives and intransitives, mind verbs (admire a person, think) favor a distributive interpretation in comparison to other verbs, consistent with (29).

Figure 4
Figure 4

Average percentage of distributive annotations for mind verbs vs. other verbs, considering both intransitives and transitives.

Strictly speaking, (29) might predict that mind verbs should all be annotated as distributive, without exception; but Figure 4 shows a tendency rather than an absolute, showing that some (confused, inattentive, or imaginative) annotators were willing to use the adverb jointly to describe situations in which two people share the same mental state.

Although the model comparison finds that mind verbs have an additive effect rather than a significant interaction with transitivity, Figure 4 shows that this effect is clearest among transitive mind verbs (love a movie). Intransitive mind verbs (think) are not much different from other intransitive verbs (walk), all favoring a distributive interpretation. In contrast, transitive mind verbs (admire a person) are strikingly more distributive than other transitive verbs (open a door).

Most transitive verbs describe events in which a subject affects an object (Hopper & Thompson 1980) but transitive mind verbs (those with experiencer subjects, such as see, love, and hate) are unique because their objects bring about a perceptual or emotional experience in their subjects (Belletti & Rizzi 1988; Dowty 1991). This paper identifies one more inferentially unique facet of mind verbs: when applied to a plural subject, mind verbs systematically favor a distributive interpretation.

To contextualize this finding, it is important to explore how transitive verbs differ from intransitive verbs more generally.

4.4 Explaining the Transitive/Intransitive asymmetry

The distinction between transitive and intransitive verbs (30) (repeated from above) has the largest effect size. Figure 5 illustrates the average percentage of distributive annotations for intransitive verbs (∼75%) compared to predicates built from transitive verbs (∼50%).

Figure 5
Figure 5

Average percentage of distributive annotations for intransitive verbs vs. predicates built from transitive verbs.

(30) Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry: Predicates built from many intransitive verbs (smile, laugh, arrive, die) are only distributive, whereas predicates built from many transitive verbs (open a door, eat a pizza) can be nondistributive.

But it may seem ironic that the prediction with the largest effect size has the least obvious theoretical motivation (§2). Why would a predicate’s potential for distributivity be related to its syntax?

We have seen that causatives favor nondistributive interpretations, and that transitive verbs are the only ones that can be causative in the sense of describing an event in which a subject causes a change on an object. I attempted a mediation analysis (Baron & Kenny 1986), testing whether the effect of transitivity is lessened when causation is included as well (on this analysis, transitivity would predict causation, which would in turn predict nondistributivity). But the effect of transitivity is scarcely lessened by including causation in the model, so the effect of transitivity is not much mediated by causation.12

Thus, even controlling for causation, transitive verbs are still starkly more likely to be annotated as nondistributive compared to intransitive verbs. Why are even the non-causative transitive verbs so much less distributive than intransitive verbs?

We find a clue among examples of the “non-causative” predicates built from transitive verbs that are still most often annotated as nondistributive (31):

(31) Predicates built from transitive verbs, not labeled as causative, annotated as nondistributive by >80% of annotators
  afford a car, announce a plan, build a house, bury a body, expose a flaw, free a country, negotiate a price, protect a child, seal a deal, steal a car, support a family, train a dog…

None of the predicates in (31) are labeled as “causative”, because none of these verbs inherits or evokes any Causation-related frame in FrameNet, nor serves as the “causative-of” any other frame. Nor do they undergo the causative-inchoative alternation (Smith 1970; Levin 1993) – I opened the door/the door opened – which serves as a sufficient-but-not-necessary diagnostic for causation.

In contrast, consider the “non-causative” predicates built from transitive verbs that are annotated as distributive by at least 70% of annotators (32):

(32) Predicates built from transitive verbs, not labeled as causative, annotated as distributive by >70% of annotators
  cross a road, don a hat, flee a country, forgive a person, hear a story, interpret a statement, learn a lesson, light a cigarette, lose a job, manifest a symptom, ponder a question, practice a religion, ride a bike, shed a tear, use a phone, violate a rule, …

Comparing (31) and (32), we observe that the mostly-nondistributive predicates in (31) tend to describe events in which the object is relatively more affected, while the mostly-distributive ones in (32) describe events in which the subject is more affected. A person who buries a body changes its location (object-affecting), while a person who crosses a road changes their own location (subject-affecting).

To generalize, we can draw on ideas from Dixon (1979); Hopper & Thompson (1980); Comrie (1989); Dowty (1991); Gropen et al. (1991); DeLancey (1991); Naigles & Kako (1993); Levin & Rappaport Hovav (2005); Næss (2007); Beavers (2011); Croft (2012) to arrange predicates along a spectrum (33) from those where the object is most affected to those where the subject is most affected. At the end of the spectrum where the object is most affected, we find the verbs defined strictly as causative (open a door) – those that participate in the causative/inchoative alternation, evoke a causation-related frame in FrameNet, and entail a change of state in their object; all the verbs at this end of the spectrum must be transitive because only transitive verbs have an object.

In the intermediate portion of the spectrum, we find different degrees of object affectedness (Beavers 2011), from those entailing a specific change in the object (open a door) to those conveying a potential for change (train a dog, scrub a pot, hit a window).

At the end of the spectrum where the subject is most affected, we find transitive verbs describing events where the subject rather than the object undergoes a change, including subject-experiencer mind verbs (I noticed a problem), and all intransitive verbs, which have no object.

(33) Object most affected………………  ………………Subject most affected
  open a door > bury a body > train a dog > notice a problem, flee a country, fall

To explain the Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry (30), we can begin by exploring differences within transitive verbs. Within transitives (33), a nondistributive interpretation is available for those describing events in which the subject affects the object (open a door, bury a body, train a dog). Whenever the object changes as a result of such an event (the door opens, the body’s location changes, the dog’s behavior changes), the subject causes that change. Any time a subject causes a change upon an object, the Causative Prediction would predict that the structure of causation should allow a nondistributive interpretation, whereby the actions of multiple individuals are jointly but not individually sufficient to cause a result. From this perspective, the Causative Prediction should apply not just to the verbs that meet the strict criteria for causatives according to FrameNet, but to all verbs describing an event in which a subject causally affects an object, including not just the pole of (33) but the whole left portion, including predicates such as (31).

In contrast, among transitive verbs describing events in which the subject is more affected (flee a country), a distributive interpretation is preferred. There is no way for the structure of causation to give rise to a nondistributive interpretation, because the subject does not affect an object; instead, it is the subject which is affected. This explanation encompasses both the subject-affecting predicates in (32) as well as the transitive mind verbs with experiencer subjects handled by the Mind Prediction (love a movie), all of which strongly favor a distributive interpretation.

As for intransitive verbs (smile, fall), all of them describe events affecting the subject. Just like subject-affecting transitive verbs, they cannot describe events in which a subject affects an object, so they cannot get a nondistributive interpretation from the structure of causation. As a result, they behave as distributive, unless they describe events that are inherently multilateral (meet).

To explain the Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry, I therefore propose that:

(34) Proposed explanation for the Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry
  a. Many transitive verbs describe events in which a subject affects (causes a change in) an object, and thus can describe an event in which multiple individuals’ joint contributions are jointly sufficient but individually insufficient to bring about a result – thus, are likely to be interpreted as nondistributive.
  b. Intransitive verbs by definition cannot describe events in which a subject affects an object, so they cannot get a nondistributive interpretation from the structure of causation – thus, are likely to be interpreted as distributive.

This explanation brings together all of the main findings of the paper. It relies upon the Causative Prediction, because the structure of causation allows that the contributions of multiple individuals may be jointly but not individually sufficient to cause a result. It also comprises the Mind Prediction; mind verbs are distributive because they describe events in which the subject rather than the object is affected. And it explains not only the Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry, but also the differences within different types of transitive verbs (31)–(32). (Transitive) verbs describing object-affecting events get a nondistributive interpretation from the nature of causation, inherent to affecting change in an object. (Transitive or intransitive) verbs describing subject-affecting events tend to receive a distributive interpretation, because causation cannot give them a nondistributive interpretation.

4.5 Further evidence that object-affectedness predicts nondistributivity

(34) can be further validated using the data of White et al. (2016), who annotate inferences (Dowty 1991) about the noun-phrase arguments of various verb tokens in the English Web Treebank. In the sentence Katrina devastated refineries in Louisiana and Mississippi, annotators rated on a 5-point Likert scale the extent to which the direct object refineries “was/were altered or somehow changed during or by the end of the devastating.” Such annotations capture the affectedness of a direct object without requiring the verb to count as strictly causative.

For each transitive verb, the average “change-of-state” Likert rating of its direct object was gathered (mean = 2.93 across all tokens and annotators; note that only 401 of my 859 transitive verbs appear in these data). Among all transitive verbs, a verb’s mean change-of-state rating is a strong negative predictor of the verb being annotated as distributive (predicting ‘annotation’ in a logistic regression as a function of change-of-state rating, with random intercepts for annotators and predicates, β = –0.21, p < 0.001), and the effect persists even when limiting the data to transitive verbs that are not labeled as causative.

In other words, even among transitive verbs that are not labeled as causative, the ones that describe object-affecting events are least likely to be annotated as distributive. I take these findings to be consistent with the claim (34) that even some not-strictly-causative transitive verbs describe events in which a subject affects (causes a change upon) an object, and that these transitive verbs favor a nondistributive interpretation just as the strictly-causative ones do.

4.6 Other predictions that turned out not significant

Some other independent variables were predicted (§2) to influence distributivity but had no statistically noticeable effect: body predicates, incremental predicates, commercial predicates, and multilateral predicates. We cannot draw strong inferences from the absence of a statistical effect. But to speculate, perhaps these predictions failed because each of these classes was quite small (none comprised more than 105 verbs, most less than 50). The incremental prediction and the commercial prediction apply exclusively to transitive verbs and predict them to favor nondistributivity – but any such effect may be washed out by the fact that most transitive verbs favor nondistributivity already. From the available evidence, it remains open whether these predictions should be re-thought, or whether they are just empirically drowned out by other factors.

4.7 Section summary

This section has found evidence consistent with several theoretically motivated predictions about how a predicate’s distributivity potential depends on the nature of the event it describes.

I have argued that the potential for distributivity crucially depends on whether the subject or the object of the verb is affected. Verbs describing object-affecting events get a nondistributive interpretation from the structure of causation, whereas verbs describing subject-affecting events cannot receive a nondistributive interpretation through these means. This explanation encompasses the Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry (only transitive verbs can describe object-affecting events), the Causative Prediction (causation is what gives object-affecting verbs a nondistributive interpretation), the Mind Prediction (mind verbs as defined here are all subject-affecting and distributive), and differences within transitive verbs (the object-affecting ones can be nondistributive, even those that are neither causatives nor mind verbs).

Many questions remain open. Why are some predictions (about body, incremental, and multilateral predicates) not manifested? In addition to the effect of a given verb, what is the effect of its particular object on the distributivity of a full predicate? But this section at least charts a path for exploring distributivity across the lexicon.

5 Semantic representations of distributivity

Turning to the formal semantics question of how distributive and nondistributive interpretations should be represented, I show that any available formal analysis must be complemented by a theory, like the one offered here, of which predicates are interpreted in which ways.

5.1 Distributivity as plurality

Landman (1989; 2000) aims to unify distributivity with plurality. For him, smile is semantically singular, like a singular count noun (child); it is lexically restricted to only apply to “atomic” individuals such as Alice. To apply to a plural subject such as Alice and Bob, smile must be simultaneously made plural and distributive using the ⋆ operator (closure under sum) from Link (1983).13 Just as pluralized children (⋆child) is true of the plural AliceBob if singular child is true of each one, pluralized ⋆smile is true of the plural AliceBob if singular, un-pluralized smile is individually true of Alice and of Bob. Among both nouns and verbs, plurality and distributivity are derived in unison from ⋆.

(35) child⟧ = {Alice, Bob}
(36) ⟦⋆child⟧ = {Alice, Bob, AliceBob}
(37) child(a) ∧ child(b) ↔ ⋆child (ab)
(38) smile⟧ = {Alice, Bob}
(39) ⟦⋆smile⟧ = {Alice, Bob, AliceBob}
(40) smile(a) ∧ smile(b) ↔ ⋆smile(ab)

Since distributive predication is synonymous with plural predication on Landman’s view, then collective (roughly, non-distributive) predication must equal singular predication. For Landman, meet is lexically restricted to only apply to “groups,” semantically singular but conceptually composite entities such as committee, which can be formed from regular plurals by Link’s group-forming ↑ operator. Meet is true of the group ↑ (AliceBob), but not individually true of each member.

(41) Alice and Bob met.
  meet (↑ (ab))

As for predicates that can be interpreted as both distributive and nondistributive, such as open the door, these are lexically allowed to apply both to atomic individuals such as Alice, and to groups such as ↑ (AliceBob). On its distributive interpretation, open the door becomes both plural and distributive via ⋆ and applies individually to Alice and to Bob as atoms; on its nondistributive interpretation, it is singular and applies to the group ↑ (AliceBob).

(42) Alice and Bob opened the door.
  a. Distributive: ⋆open the door (a ⊕ b)
  b. Collective: open the door (↑ (a ⊕ b))

Landman’s analysis faithfully represents the inferences drawn from smile, meet, and open the door, but does not explain or predict which predicates are understood in which ways. Smile is said to be lexically restricted to atoms, meet to groups; open the door can apply to both atoms and groups. These facts, which derive the distributivity potential of such predicates, presumably depend on lexical/world knowledge about the events they describe (i.e., the fact that people have their own faces and so can only smile individually), in ways open to be explored.

For Landman, therefore, the current study helps explain which further predicates lexically apply to atoms, groups, or both.

5.2 Meaning postulates and a D operator

The literature’s most common approach to distributivity (Roberts 1987; Dowty 1987; Link 1991; Lasersohn 1995; Link 1998; Winter 2000; Champollion 2010; de Vries 2015; Champollion 2017; de Vries 2017) is two-pronged, involving both meaning postulates (Carnap 1952; Scha 1981) and a silent version of each known as the D operator (Link 1991, originally written in the 1980s; Roberts 1987).14 Meaning postulates are stipulated restrictions on the models entertained in a model-theoretic framework, used to capture lexical/world knowledge. D is an optional, silent, scope-taking operator, ambiguously present or absent, which guarantees distributivity when present.

To illustrate with the influential version of Champollion (2010), smile is distributive because a meaning postulate requires us to only consider models where every member of a plural who smiles does so individually: whenever a group G smiles, its members do so too.

(43) Alice and Bob smiled.
  smile(AliceBob)
  Meaning postulate: smile(G) → ∀ x[xGsmile(x)]

Meet is nondistributive because it has no such meaning postulate (and perhaps also thanks to the group-forming ↑ operator of Link 1983, which some authors in this tradition invoke in addition to other tools).

(44) Alice and Bob met.
  meet(AliceBob)
  (or, if using ↑:) meet(↑(AliceBob))

Open the door is understood in both ways because it is ambiguous between a representation with the D operator (45a) (silent each) and one without (45b). The nondistributive version, without D, might or might not also be analyzed to include the group-forming ↑ operator.

(45) Alice and Bob opened the door.
  a. Distributive: Alice and Bob D(opened the door).
  b. Nondistributive/Collective: ↑(Alice and Bob) opened the door.

All inferences about distributivity are derived formally from a combination of meaning postulates, D, and possibly also ↑.

To clarify some terminology: distributive inferences attributed to meaning postulates are also termed “P(redicate)-distributivity” (Winter 1997; de Vries 2015; 2017) or “lexical distributivity” (Champollion 2010; 2017) because these inferences are pinned to the meaning of a particular predicate or lexical item, and because the prototypical examples (smile) consist of a single lexical item; such inferences are predicted to be consistent and non-optional because the lexical item requires them. In contrast, distributive inferences attributed to D are termed “Q(uantificational)-distributivity” (Winter 1997; de Vries 2015; 2017) or ‘phrasal distributivity’ (Champollion 2010; 2017), because a predicate combined with a (quantificational) operator constitutes a syntactically complex phrase, and because the prototypical examples (open a door, build a raft) involve syntactically complex phrases; such inferences are optional because D itself is optional. (As for non-prototypical examples – such as win, a one-word “lexical” predicate which can be both distributive and nondistributive; or see the photo, a consistently distributive “phrasal” predicate – the labels of lexical and phrasal distributivity are harder to assign.)15

In sum, smile is required to be distributive by a meaning postulate; meet is not; open the door is ambiguous because D might or might not be present. It is left open which meaning postulates are needed and why, as well as with which predicates the distributive operator D and the collective operator ↑ would be redundant, consequential, or incompatible. Presumably these questions depend on lexical/world knowledge about the events described by such predicates, in ways that remain to be explored.

The current study thus would help explain which further predicates should have a distributive meaning postulate, and which ones should ambiguously combine with D or not. Moreover, the Transitive/Intransitive asymmetry also grounds the observation, fundamental to the two-pronged approach, that most “lexical” predicates built from intransitive verbs are consistently distributive (smile), whereas many “phrasal” predicates built from transitive verbs (open a door) have both interpretations available.

5.3 Covers

On a third type of analysis (Higginbotham 1981; Gillon 1987; Schwarzschild 1996), a predicate applied to a plural is individually true of each cell of a contextually supplied cover – set of subparts – of the subject. Covers were initially used to deal with so-called non-atomic distributivity (Gillon 1987; Lasersohn 1995; 1998; Wohlmuth 2019), when a predicate distributes down to plural sub-groups of a plural subject, as in the shoes cost $50 (Lasersohn 1998) where cost $50 is interpreted so that each pair of shoes occupies its own cell of the cover. But the idea of covers can handle all distributive and nondistributive interpretations of sentences, atomic as well as non-atomic.

When the sentential subject comprises two conjoined names (Alice and Bob), there are two possible cover settings: one placing each member of the subject in its own cell of the cover (distributive, because the predicate is true of Alice and of Bob); and one placing both of them into the same cell (nondistributive, because the predicate is true of Alice and Bob together but not each one individually).16 This analysis treats smile, meet, and open the door in a uniform way: each predicate is true of each cell of some contextually supplied cover of the subject. Different inferences are drawn from smile, meet, and open the door because different covers are entertained for each predicate, given what is known about the events they describe.

For smile, the only sensible cover is one placing each member of the subject into its own cell (distributive), given that individuals have their own faces and cannot smile jointly. As for the notation, Cov(AliceBob) represents the set of cells of the contextually supplied cover of the plural Alice and Bob. Smile(e) ∧ agent(e, x) indicates that e is a smiling event whose agent is x, using the neo-Davidsonian event semantics of Higginbotham (1985) and Parsons (1990), building on Davidson (1967). (46) ensures that Alice and Bob are each the agent of their own smiling event.

(46) Alice and Bob smiled.
  x[xCov(AliceBob) → ∃e[smile(e) ∧ agent(e, x)]]
  a. ✓Distributive: they each smiled
    Cov = { {a }, {b} }
  b. ✗Nondistributive: they smiled jointly but not individually
    Cov = { {a, b} }

For meet, the only sensible cover is one placing both members of the subject in the same cell (nondistributive), given that individuals cannot meet individually. (47) describes a single meet event, with Alice and Bob together as its agent.

(47) Alice and Bob met.
  x[xCov(AliceBob) → ∃e[meet(e) ∧ agent(e, x)]]
  a. ✗Distributive: they each met
    Cov = { {a }, {b} }
  b. ✓Nondistributive: they met jointly but not individually
    Cov = { {a, b} }

Finally, for open the door, both available covers are sensible – one placing each member of the subject into their own cell (distributive), one placing them into the same cell (nondistributive) – given that people can open doors individually or jointly.

(48) Alice and Bob opened the door.
  x[xCov(AliceBob) → ∃e[open(e) ∧ agent(e, x) ∧ theme(e, ι y[door(y)])]]
  a. ✓Distributive: they each opened it
    Cov = { {a }, {b} }
  b. ✓Nondistributive: they opened it jointly but not individually
    Cov = { {a, b} }

On this proposal, all three predicates – smile, meet, and open the door – are given the same semantics: true of each cell of a contextually supplied cover of the subject. Where they differ is in their pragmatics: different covers are entertained for each predicate, given what is known about these events. Like all the others, this formalism tells only part of the story:

“This [analysis in terms of pragmatically determined covers] leaves us with […] a pragmatic theory of distributivity, which, along with other pragmatic phenomena, requires further analysis both in and outside of linguistics.” – Schwarzschild 1996: 101

On this approach, the current study would help to explain which covers are chosen for which predicates.

5.4 Section summary

There are various ways to formalize the inferences drawn from smile, meet, and open the door. But none of them explains which other predicates will behave like smile, like meet, like open the door, or why. We also need to explain, as this paper has tried to, what inferences we want to formalize: which interpretations are available for which predicates.

6 Conclusion

To explain how people understand sentences with plural subjects, researchers face two questions:

  1. The lexical semantics question: Which predicates are interpreted as distributive and/or nondistributive, and why?

  2. The formal semantics question: How should distributivity be represented formally?

Addressing the lexical semantics question, the paper has motivated some predictions about the distributivity potential of various predicates, and shown that these are manifested in a large dataset: the Causative Prediction and the Mind Prediction. Using the notion of object-affectedness, the paper has also offered an explanation of the Transitive/Intransitive Asymmetry – the observation that predicates built from transitive verbs favor a nondistributive interpretation, whereas those built from intransitive verbs tend to be distributive. It is argued that object-affecting transitive verbs favor nondistributivity because they describe events in which a subject causes a change upon an object; the structure of causation allows that multiple individuals’ contributions may be jointly sufficient but individually insufficient to bring about a result.

More generally, any time a semantic phenomenon depends on lexical/world knowledge, the challenge is to explain what such knowledge matters and why. This paper has aimed to take on that challenge to offer a more predictive view of this phenomenon.

As for the formal semantics question, the paper has argued that any formal analysis ends up leaving the explanatory work to lexical/world knowledge about how members of the subject can participate in the event described by the predicate, highlighting the need for an answer to the lexical semantics question.

Zooming out, distributivity has traditionally been studied as a topic for formal semantics, aiming to explain a small group of clear-cut examples. Here, I have treated it as a topic for lexical semantics, still illustrating with a handful of clear-cut examples but also aiming to explain a wider range of data. This approach aims to take up the challenge set out by Winter & Scha (2015):

“We would like to reiterate the importance that we see for a rigorous theory about the lexicon and the pragmatics of plurals, especially in relation to […] distributivity […]. More general and precise theories of these lexical and pragmatic domains will also surely shed more light on the compositional semantics of plurality.” – Winter & Scha (2015): 35

Distributivity is defined by the observation that different predicates (smile, meet, open the door) act different from one another, making it a lexical semantics topic from the start. I hope to have shown that it is illuminated when treated as one.

Additional file

The additional file for this article can be found as follows:

Notes

  1. Nondistributive interpretations are also called collective (Scha 1981; Link 1983; Landman 1989), a term which may evoke elusive inferences about joint responsibility and collaboration (Landman 2000) and a contentious distinction between “collective” versus “cumulative” interpretations (Landman 2000; Kratzer 2007; Champollion 2010). To avoid those issues, I simply contrast distributive interpretations with non-distributive ones (Roberts 1987; Schwarzschild 1996; Link 1998). [^]
  2. More formally, this prediction can be derived from a widespread theoretical assumption (Krifka 1992; Kratzer 2007; Champollion 2010) that verbs and thematic roles are “cumulative” in the sense of being closed under sum formation. A verb such as eat can be analyzed as a set of eating events, as in (i) (where events are represented as tuples consisting of a label for the event and its thematic roles). Then, for any two events e1 and e2 in this set, the cumulativity assumption requires that their sum e1 ⊕ e2 is also in this set. The sum of two eat events is also an eat event; its agent is the sum of the agent of e1 and the agent of e2, and its theme is the sum of the theme of e1 and the theme of e2. This setup guarantees the natural result that if Alice eats half the pizza and Bob eats the other half, then Alice and Bob eat the full pizza between them.
    (i) ⟦eat⟧ = {⟨e1, agent = Alice, theme = half the pizza1⟩,
        e2, agent=Bob, theme=half the pizza2⟩,
        e1 ⊕ e2, agent = AliceBob, theme = half the pizza1half the pizza2⟩}
    [^]
  3. There are apparent exceptions to (17), such as Lasersohn’s example, The committees met (Lasersohn 1988), which can be distributive (each committee meets alone). But this exception actually proves the rule; committees can meet individually in a way that individual humans cannot. [^]
  4. In a linear regression predicting the percentage of distributive annotations for a predicate as a function of the mean z-scored 2018 “each” rating of a predicate built from that same verb, β = 0.12, p < 0.001. Using the mean z-scored 2018 “together” rating as a predictor instead, β = –0.13, p < 0.001. [^]
  5. https://files.pushshift.io/reddit/comments/. [^]
  6. There were some exceptions to this general rule; among verbs that rarely have a direct object, some were still classified as transitive if their intransitive argument structure does not make sense when applied to a human subject. Tend rarely has a direct object (its complement is usually a nonfinite clause), but was classified as transitive because Alice and Bob tended a bar is more sensible than Alice and Bob tended. [^]
  7. FrameNet can be explored through its web demo: https://framenet.icsi.berkeley.edu/. [^]
  8. As for the labels that turned out not to be significant, a predicate was labeled as a “body” predicate if it evokes or inherits the frames SELF-MOTION, BODY-MOVEMENT, SLEEP, DEATH, MAKING-FACES, or EXPERIENCE-BODILY-HARM. In total, 103 predicates were labeled as “body” predicates (69 transitives, 34 intransitives), including:
    (i) blink, back a claim, dance, duck, hop, hurry, jump, jog, chase a car, close a door, hit a wall, march, move, nod, reach a goal, shake a bottle, shrug a responsibility, stub a toe, walk, …
    Some predicates may seem to be mis-labeled (back a claim, shrug a responsibility do not really seem to involve the body), but back evokes the SELF-MOTION frame (e.g., back up) and shrug inherit the BODY-MOVEMENT frame, so they are labeled as “body” predicates. In general, automatic labeling is rarely perfect, but cannot be corrected by hand without risking bias from the researcher. A predicate was labeled as “commercial” if it evokes or inherits the frames GIVING, POSSESSION, BRINGING, SENDING, COMMERCE-BUY, or COMMERCE-SELL. In total, 43 predicates were labeled as “commercial” (all transitive), including:
    (ii) donate a dollar, gift a car, lend a car, mail a check, own a gun, pay a bill, provide an example, sell a car, supply a drug, …
    A predicate was labeled as “incremental” if it involves a transitive verb (because incremental predicates, as defined here, describe events in which a subject incrementally affects an object) and evokes or inherits the frames INGESTION or INTENTIONALLY-CREATE. In total, 42 predicates were labeled as “incremental” (all transitive), including:
    (iii) bake a cake, consume an alcohol, drink a beer, draw a picture, ingest a pill, produce a result, sign a contract, write a book, …
    A predicate was labeled as “multilateral” if it evokes or inherits the RECIPROCITY or COME-TOGETHER frames. (In some cases, only the intransitive frame of the verb actually describes a reciprocal relation between members of a plural subject, as in they met, while the transitive frame describes such a relation between the subject and and object, as in they met me; but there are other cases where even the transitive frame of the verb describes a reciprocal relation between members of a plural subject, as in they exchanged an email.) In total, 21 predicates were labeled as “multilateral” (15 transitive, 6 intransitive), including:
    (iv) chat, differ, exchange an email, meet a friend, share a story, trade a stock, talk, unite a tribe, vary, …
    [^]
  9. A twenty-first list was also added, for five predicates that had mistakenly been left out of the original twenty lists. [^]
  10. Initially, 90 annotators were run in May 2020; an additional 125 were added in October 2020, for 215 total. This study was declared officially exempt from the IRB by my institution’s IRB board. [^]
  11. Code from T. Florian Jaeger (https://hlplab.wordpress.com/2011/02/24/diagnosing-collinearity-in-lme4/) was used to calculate the Variance Inflation Factor (VIF) for each independent variable, as a test for collinearity. VIF measures the extent to which one independent variable is correlated with others (too much collinearity is a problem, indicating that one variable is perhaps redundant with another). The VIF scores are:
    (i) a. transitive: 1.05
      b. mind: 1.03
      c. causative: 1.07
    A VIF score around 1 indicates minimal collinearity with another independent variable. Thus, while all causatives are transitive, (i) shows that these two variables are still not too collinear. [^]
  12. A model that considers both transitivity and causation predicts a (non-causative) transitive verb to have a 51% chance of being annotated as distributive; a model that considers only transitivity predicts it to have a 49% chance of being annotated as distributive. Please see my full R code, available on the Open Science Framework (https://osf.io/ena5r/), for the full mediation analysis. [^]
  13. P is the closure under sum of a set P; if Alice and Bob are in the unpluralized set of individuals who smile, then their sum AliceBob is in the pluralized ⋆smile. Landman further assumes that un-pluralized smile applies only to individual atoms, and that the pluralizing star applies only to predicates that in their singular form are restricted to atoms. Thus, if the sum AliceBob is in the denotation of pluralized ⋆smile, it follows that the atoms Alice and Bob are members of the un-pluralized smile, and vice versa. [^]
  14. Some authors subsume D under the pluralizing ⋆operator of Landman (1989; 2000); but other authors keep D separate from ⋆. Particularly, some researchers (Kratzer 2007; Champollion 2010) assume that all verbs and thematic roles are closed under sum formation (“cumulative”), and use ⋆ to represent that assumption – but they do not intend this use of ⋆ to convey distributivity. [^]
  15. The distinction between one-word and multi-word predicates also comes up in the literature on collectivity (Winter 2000; Kuhn 2020), where one-word collective predicates (gather) are found to differ from multi-word collective predicates (form a good team), for reasons open to be explored:
    (i) a. (All) the students gathered.
      b. (?All) the students form a good team.
    [^]
  16. The chosen cover should also be the tightest-fitting one – one where no cover with more fine-grained cells would be accurate. Without this stipulation, (46a) and (46b) might both be equally good covers in a situation where Alice and Bob each smiled – (46a) because each of them smiled, and (46b) because, if we adopt a widespread assumption that verbs and thematic roles are closed under sum formation (“cumulative”; Krifka 1992, Kratzer 2007, Champollion 2010), then if there is a smiling event by Alice and a smiling event by Bob, there is also a larger smiling event by AliceBob. By requiring the tightest-fitting Cover, (46a) is chosen over (46b) when Alice and Bob each smiled. [^]

Ethics and consent

Annotators on Mechanical Turk participated in the study after agreeing to a consent form written in consultation with the Georgia Tech Institutional Review Board. Annotators all used United States I.P. addresses and were paid $3.00 for what amounted to between seven and fifteen minutes of work. Because the annotators were anonymous and provided no personal data, this study received an official exemption from the Georgia Tech Institutional Review Board.

Acknowledgements

For constructive feedback and inspiring conversations, I am very grateful to the advisors of my 2018 Stanford dissertation, the antecedent of this work: Beth Levin, Christopher Potts, Cleo Condoravdi, and Daniel Lassiter; to the Editor (Min-Joo Kim) and three anonymous reviewers at Glossa as well as to three earlier reviewers at Journal of Linguistics; and to Lucas Champollion, Yoad Winter, and Hanna de Vries. I thank Aaron Steven White and Will Gantt for conversations which helped me to redesign the annotation study, and Kathy Dahlgren and Karen Wallace at Nuance Communications for first inspiring me to work on distributivity. I am also indebted to all the audiences before whom the work has been presented. Errors are mine.

Funding information

This work was partially supported by awards from the American Council for Learned Societies Mellon Dissertation Fellowship, Phi Beta Kappa of California, and the Vice Provost for Graduate Education at Stanford University, as well as by research funding from the School of Modern Languages at Georgia Institute of Technology. The support is gratefully acknowledged.

Competing interests

The author has no competing interests to declare.

References

Baker, Collin F., Charles J. Fillmore & John B. Lowe. 1998. The Berkeley FrameNet project. In Proceedings of the 17th international conference on computational linguistics, 86–90. Association for Computational Linguistics. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3115/980845.980860

Baron, Reuben M. & David A. Kenny. 1986. The moderator–mediator variable distinction in social psychological research: Conceptual, strategic, and statistical considerations. Journal of personality and social psychology 51(6). 1173–1182. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.51.6.1173

Barr, Dale J., Roger Levy, Christoph Scheepers & Harry J. Tily. 2013. Random effects structure for confirmatory hypothesis testing: Keep it maximal. Journal of Memory and Language 68(3). 255–278. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/j.jml.2012.11.001

Bartsch, Renate. 1973. The semantics and syntax of number and numbers. In John Kimball (ed.), Syntax and semantics 2. 51–93. New York: Seminar Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1163/9789004368804_003

Bates, Douglas, Martin Mächler, Ben Bolker & Steve Walker. 2015. Fitting linear mixed-effects models using lme4. Journal of Statistical Software 67(1). 1–48. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.18637/jss.v067.i01

Beavers, John. 2011. On affectedness. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 29(2). 335–370. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-011-9124-6

Belletti, Adriana & Luigi Rizzi. 1988. Psych verbs and θ-theory. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 6(3). 291–352. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00133902

Brisson, Christine. 2003. Plurals, ‘all’, and the nonuniformity of collective predication. Linguistics and Philosophy 26(2). 129–184. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1022771705575

Brooks, Patricia J. & Martin D. Braine. 1996. What do children know about the universal quantifiers all and each? Cognition 60(3). 235–268. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(96)00712-3

Carlson, Greg. 1998. Thematic roles and the individuation of events. In Susan Rothstein (ed.), Events and grammar, 35–51. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3969-4_3

Carnap, Rudolf. 1952. Meaning postulates. Philosophical studies 3(5). 65–73. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/BF02350366

Champollion, Lucas. 2010. Parts of a whole: Distributivity as a bridge between aspect and measurement. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania dissertation.

Champollion, Lucas. 2016. Covert distributivity in algebraic event semantics. Semantics and Pragmatics 9. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/sp.9.15

Champollion, Lucas. 2017. Parts of a whole: Distributivity as a bridge between aspect and measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198755128.001.0001

Champollion, Lucas. 2019. Distributivity in formal semantics. Annual Review of Linguistics 5. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-linguistics-011718-012528

Champollion, Lucas. 2020. Distributivity, collectivity, and cumulativity. In Daniel Gutzmann, Lisa Matthewson, Cécile Meier, Hotze Rullmann & Thomas Ede Zimmermann (eds.), Wiley blackwell companion to semantics, Hoboken: Wiley Blackwell. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1002/9781118788516

Comrie, Bernard. 1989. Language universals and linguistic typology, second edition. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Copley, Bridget & Phillip Wolff. 2014. Theories of causation should inform linguistic theory and vice versa. In Bridget Copley & Fabienne Martin (eds.), Causation in grammatical structures, 11–57. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199672073.003.0002

Corblin, Francis. 2008. Des prédicats non-quantifiables: les prédicats holistes. Langages 1. 34–56. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3917/lang.169.0034

Croft, William. 2012. Verbs: Aspect and causal structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199248582.001.0001

Davidson, Donald. 1967. The logical form of action sentences. In Nicholas Rescher (ed.), The logic of decision and action, 81–95. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/0199246270.003.0006

de Vries, Hanna. 2015. Shifting sets, hidden atoms: The semantics of distributivity, plurality and animacy. Utrecht: Utrecht University dissertation.

de Vries, Hanna. 2017. Two kinds of distributivity. Natural Language Semantics 25(2). 173–197. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-017-9133-z

DeLancey, Scott. 1991. Event construal and case role assignment. In Laurel A. Sutton, Christopher Johnson & Ruth Shields (eds.), Berkeley linguistics society (BLS) 17. 338–353. Ann Arbor: Braun-Brumfield, Inc. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/bls.v17i0.1610

Dixon, R. M. W. 1979. Ergativity. Language 55(1). 59–138. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.2307/412519

Dobrovie-Sorin, Carmen, Emilia Ellsiepen & Barbara Hemforth. 2016. Why are distributive readings dispreferred? In Ernestina Carrilho, Alexandra Fiéis, Maria Lobo & Sandra Pereira (eds.), Romance languages and linguistic theory 10: Selected papers from ‘going romance’ 28, 83–102. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/rllt.10.05dob

Dotlačil, Jakub. 2010. Anaphora and distributivity: A study of same, different, reciprocals and others. Utrecht: Utrecht University dissertation.

Dowty, David R. 1979. Word meaning and Montague grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9473-7

Dowty, David R. 1987. A note on collective predicates, distributive predicates, and ‘all’. In Fred Marshall, Ann Miller & Zheng-sheng Zhang (eds.), Eastern states conference on linguistics (ESCOL) 3. 97–116. Columbus: The Ohio State University.

Dowty, David R. 1991. Thematic proto-roles and argument selection. Language 67(3). 547–619. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.1991.0021

Fillmore, Charles J. 1969. Types of lexical information. In Ferenc Kiefer (ed.), Studies in syntax and semantics, 109–137. Dordrecht: Reidel. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1707-7_6

Fillmore, Charles J. 1970. The grammar of hitting and breaking. In Roderick Jacobs & Peter Rosenbaum (eds.), Readings in english transformational grammar, 120–33. Washington: Georgetown University Press.

Fillmore, Charles J. 1976. Frame semantics and the nature of language. In Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences: Conference on the origin and development of language and speech 280. 20–32. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1749-6632.1976.tb25467.x

Frazier, Lyn, Jeremy M. Pacht & Keith Rayner. 1999. Taking on semantic commitments, ii: Collective versus distributive readings. Cognition 70(1). 87–104. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(99)00002-5

Gillon, Brendan S. 1987. The readings of plural noun phrases in English. Linguistics and Philosophy 10(2). 199–219. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00584318

Glass, Lelia. 2018a. Deriving the distributivity potential of adjectives via measurement theory. In Patrick Ferrell (ed.), Linguistic society of america (LSA), 3. Washington, DC: Linguistic Society of America. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/plsa.v3i1.4343

Glass, Lelia. 2018b. Distributivity, lexical semantics, and world knowledge. Stanford University dissertation. http://ling.auf.net/lingbuzz/004050.

Grafmiller, Jason. 2013. The semantics of syntactic choice: An analysis of english emotion verbs. Stanford University dissertation.

Gropen, Jess, Steven Pinker, Michelle Hollander & Richard Goldberg. 1991. Affectedness and direct objects: The role of lexical semantics in the acquisition of verb argument structure. Cognition 41(1). 153–195. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(91)90035-3

Gruber, Jeffrey S. 1965. Studies in lexical relations. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology dissertation.

Harley, Heidi & Rolf Noyer. 1999. State-of-the-article: Distributed morphology. Glot International 4(4). 3–9. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110890952.463

Herring, Susan C., Dieter Stein & Tuija Virtanen. 2013. Introduction to the pragmatics of computer-mediated communication. In Susan C. Herring, Dieter Stein & Tuija Virtanen (eds.), Pragmatics of computer-mediated communication, 3–32. Berlin: Mouton De Gruyter. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/mc-2015-0016

Higginbotham, James. 1981. Reciprocal interpretation. Journal of Linguistic Research 1(3). 97–117. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/tlir.1981.1.1.41

Higginbotham, James. 1985. On semantics. Linguistic Inquiry 16(4). 547–594.

Honnibal, Matthew & Mark Johnson. 2015. An improved non-monotonic transition system for dependency parsing. In Proceedings of the 2015 conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, 1373–78. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.18653/v1/D15-1162

Hopper, Paul J. & Sandra A. Thompson. 1980. Transitivity in grammar and discourse. Language 56(2). 251–99. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.2307/413757

Hume, David. 1748. Enquiries concerning the human understanding: And concerning the principles of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press (1902). DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/oseo/instance.00046349

Kratzer, Angelika. 2007. On the plurality of verbs. In Johannes Dölling, Tatjana Heyde-Zybatow & Martin Schäfer (eds.), Event structures in linguistic form and interpretation, 269–300. Berlin: De Gruyter. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110925449.269

Krifka, Manfred. 1992. Thematic relations as links between nominal reference and temporal constitution. In Ivan A. Sag & Anna Szabolcsi (eds.), Lexical matters, 29–54. Stanford, CA: CSLI (Center for the Study of Language and Information) Publications.

Križ, Manuel. 2016. Homogeneity, non-maximality, and ‘all’. Journal of Semantics 3(33). 493–539. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffv006

Kruitwagen, Imke, Eva B. Poortman & Yoad Winter. 2017. Reciprocal verbs as collective predicate concepts. In Andrew Lamont & Katerina Tetzloff (eds.), North east linguistic society (NELS), 47. Amherst: Graduate Linguistics Student Association of the University of Massachusetts.

Kuhn, Jeremy. 2020. Gather/numerous as a mass/count opposition. Natural Language Semantics, 1–29. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-020-09163-x

Landman, Fred. 1989. Groups, I. Linguistics and Philosophy 12(5). 559–605. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00627774

Landman, Fred. 2000. Events and plurality: The Jerusalem lectures. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-4359-2

Lasersohn, Peter. 1988. A semantics for groups and events. Columbus: The Ohio State University dissertation.

Lasersohn, Peter. 1995. Plurality, conjunction and events. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8581-1

Lasersohn, Peter. 1998. Generalized distributivity operators. Linguistics and Philosophy 21(1). 83–93. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1005317815339

Levin, Beth. 1993. English verb classes and alternations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Levin, Beth & Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1994. A preliminary analysis of causative verbs in English. Lingua 92. 35–77. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/0024-3841(94)90337-9

Levin, Beth & Malka Rappaport Hovav. 2005. Argument realization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511610479

Lewis, David. 1973. Causation. The Journal of Philosophy 70(17). 556–567. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.2307/2025310

Link, Godehard. 1983. The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A latticetheoretical approach. In Rainer Bäuerle, Christoph Schwarze & Arnim von Stechow (eds.), Meaning, use and interpretation of language, 127–146. Berlin: De Gruyter. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110852820.302

Link, Godehard. 1991. Plural. In Arnim von Stechow & Dieter Wunderlich (eds.), Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenoessischen Forschung [Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research], Berlin: De Gruyter. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110126969.6.418

Link, Godehard. 1998. Algebraic semantics in language and philosophy. Stanford: CSLI (Center for the Study of Language and Information) Publications.

Löbner, Sebastian. 2000. Polarity in natural language: Predication, quantification and negation in particular and characterizing sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy 23(3). 213–308. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1005571202592

Loper, Edward & Steven Bird. 2002. NLTK: The natural language toolkit. In Proceedings of the association for computational linguistics (acl). DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3115/1118108.1118117

Mackie, John L. 1965. Causes and conditions. American philosophical quarterly 2(4). 245–264.

McNally, Louise. 2005. Lexical representation and modification within the noun phrase. Recherches Linguistiques de Vincennes 34. 191–206. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.4000/rlv.1395

Menzies, Peter. 2014. Counterfactual theories of causation. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University spring 2014 edn.

Moltmann, Friederike. 2004. The semantics of ‘together’. Natural Language Semantics 12(4). 289–318. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-004-6453-6

Næss, Åshild. 2007. Prototypical transitivity. John Benjamins Publishing. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/tsl.72

Naigles, Letitia & Edward T. Kako. 1993. First contact in verb acquisition: Defining a role for syntax. Child Development 64(6). 1665–1687. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.2307/1131462

Nouwen, Rick. 2015. Plurality. In Paul Dekker & Maria Aloni (eds.), Cambridge handbook of semantics, 267–284. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139236157.010

Parsons, Terence. 1990. Events in the semantics of English: A study in subatomic semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Peeters, Bert. 2000. Setting the scene: Some recent milestones in the lexiconencyclopedia debate. In Bert Peeters (ed.), The lexicon-encyclopedia interface, 1–52. New York: Elsevier.

Poortman, Eva B., Marijn E. Struiksma, Nir Kerem, Naama Friedmann & Yoad Winter. 2018. Reciprocal expressions and the maximal typicality hypothesis. Glossa 3(1). DOI:  http://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.180

Powell, Michael J. D. 2009. The bobyqa algorithm for bound constrained optimization without derivatives. Cambridge NA Report NA2009/06, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, 26–46.

Pustejovsky, James. 1995. The generative lexicon. Cambridge: MIT Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/3225.001.0001

R Core Team. 2012. R: A language and environment for statistical computing. Vienna, Austria: R Foundation for Statistical Computing. http://www.R-project.org/. ISBN3-900051-07-0.

Rappaport Hovav, Malka. 2008. Lexicalized meaning and the internal structure of events. In Susan Rothstein (ed.), Theoretical and crosslinguistic approaches to the semantics of aspect, 13–42. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/la.110.03hov

Rappaport Hovav, Malka & Beth Levin. 2010. Reflections on manner/result complementarity. In Edit Doron, Malka Rappaport Hovav & Ivy Sichel (eds.), Syntax, lexical semantics, and event structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199544325.001.0001

Roberts, Craige. 1987. Modal subordination, anaphora, and distributivity. Amherst: University of Massachusetts dissertation.

Scha, Remko. 1981. Distributive, collective and cumulative quantification. In Jeroen Groenendijk & Martin Stockhof (eds.), Formal methods in the study of language, 483–512. Amsterdam: Mathematical Center Tracts. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110867602.131

Schank, Roger C. & Robert Abelson. 1977. Scripts, plans, goals, and understanding: An inquiry into human knowledge structures. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.4324/9780203781036

Schneider, Nathan & Chuck Wooters. 2017. The NLTK FrameNet API: Designing for discoverability with a rich linguistic resource. In Proceedings of the conference on empirical methods in natural language processing: System demonstrations. Copenhagen, Denmark: Association for Computational Linguistics. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.18653/v1/D17-2001

Schwarzschild, Roger. 1996. Pluralities. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2704-4

Scontras, Gregory & Noah Goodman. 2017. Resolving uncertainty in plural predication. Cognition 168. 294–311. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2017.07.002

Siloni, Tal. 2012. Reciprocal verbs and symmetry. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 30(1). 261–320. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-011-9144-2

Smith, Carlota S. 1970. Jespersen’s ‘move and change’ class and causative verbs in English. In Mohammad A. Jazayery, Edgar C. Polomé & Werner Winter (eds.), Linguistic and literary studies in honor of archibald a. hill, vol. 2: Descriptive Linguistics, 101–109. The Hague: Mouton. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110800432.101

Swanson, Eric. 2012. The language of causation. In Delia Graff Fara & Gillian Russell (eds.), The Routledge companion to the philosophy of language, 716–712. London: Routledge.

Syrett, Kristen & Julien Musolino. 2013. Collectivity, distributivity, and the interpretation of plural numerical expressions in child and adult language. Language Acquisition 20(4). 259–291. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1080/10489223.2013.828060

Tenny, Carol L. 1987. Grammaticalizing aspect and affectedness. Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology dissertation.

White, Aaron Steven, Dee Ann Reisinger, Keisuke Sakaguchi, Tim Vieira, Sheng Zhang, Rachel Rudinger, Kyle Rawlins & Benjamin Van Durme. 2016. Universal decompositional semantics on universal dependencies. In Proceedings of the 2016 conference on empirical methods in natural language processing (EMNLP), 1713–1723. Austin, Texas. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.18653/v1/D16-1177

Winter, Bodo. 2013. Linear models and linear mixed effects models in r with linguistic applications. University of California, Merced, tutorial. Available at http://arxiv.org/pdf/1308.5499.pdf.

Winter, Yoad. 1997. Choice functions and the scopal semantics of indefinites. Linguistics and Philosophy 20(4). 399–467. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1005354323136

Winter, Yoad. 2000. Distributivity and dependency. Natural Language Semantics 8(1). 27–69. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008313715103

Winter, Yoad. 2002. Atoms and sets: A characterization of semantic number. Linguistic Inquiry 33(3). 493–505. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1162/002438902760168581

Winter, Yoad. 2018. Symmetric predicates and the semantics of reciprocal alternations. Semantics and Pragmatics 11. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/sp.11.1

Winter, Yoad & Remko Scha. 2015. Plurals. In Shalom Lappin & Chris Fox (eds.), Handbook of contemporary semantic theory, 77–113. New York: Wiley 2nd edn. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1002/9781118882139.ch3

Wohlmuth, Kata. 2019. Atomicity and distributive reference. Barcelona: Universitat Pompeu Fabra dissertation.

Yoon, Youngeun. 1996. Total and partial predicates and the weak and strong interpretations. Natural Language Semantics 4(3). 217–236. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00372820