1 Introduction

We report the result of an experiment testing the difference in meaning between German auch (‘also’) vs. noch (‘in addition’, ‘still’). Both can be used as additive particles (Eckardt 2007; Umbach 2012), cf. Umbach’s examples in (1).

    1. (1)
    1. (Otto hat ein Bier getrunken. ‘Otto had a beer.’)
    1. Otto
    2. Otto
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. auch/noch
    2. also/still
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. SCHNAPS
    2. schnaps
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. ‘Otto also had a schnaps.’/‘Otto had a schnaps in addition.’

Grubic (2018), following Eckardt (2007); Umbach (2012), proposed that both additive particles indicate that a previously answered question under discussion (QUD) (What did Otto drink?) is re-opened in order to add a further answer. Grubic proposed they differ in that with auch, the two QUDs are usually about the same topic situation, whereas in the case of noch, the QUDs are obligatorily about a different topic situation. When the topic situation is overtly shifted using a temporal adverbial such as last year in (2), this account predicts a difference in accommodation behavior: for auch, which can relate propositions about the same topic situation, it is expected that hearers can accommodate that the prementioned proposition (Bertha walked the first 11 stages) is true in the second topic situation, too. Thus with auch, (2) is predicted to suggest that Bertha walked all 32 stages last year. For noch, which relates propositions about different topic situations, no accommodation of this kind is predicted.

    1. (2)
    1. (Five years ago, Bertha walked the first eleven stages of the Way of St. James. Then she unfortunately had to discontinue her pilgrimage because of an injury.)
    1. Letztes
    2. last
    1. Jahr
    2. year
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. sie
    2. she
    1. auch/noch
    2. also/still
    1. die
    2. the
    1. letzten
    2. last
    1. 21
    2. 21
    1. Etappen
    2. stages
    1. gelaufen.
    2. walked
    1. ‘Last year, she (also) walked the last 21 stages.’
    2. AUCH → she walked 11 stages five years ago and all 32 stages last year
    3. NOCH → she walked 11 stages five years ago and 21 stages last year

We report the results of an experiment testing this intuition. §2 summarizes the previous literature concerning the difference between auch and noch. The results of a pre-experiment (testing the plausibility of the presupposition to be accommodated) and our main experiment are reported in §3. Grubic’s (2018) account predicts, first, that noch should be degraded in items where accommodation is most plausible. Second, auch should be felicitous in all items, but its interpretation (accommodation/non-accommodation) should change depending on the plausibility of accommodation. Both hypotheses were confirmed in our experiment, suggesting that noch, but not auch, requires a change in topic situation. In §4, we provide a QUD account capturing this generalization. In §5, we discuss some open issues. §6 provides a summary.

2 Literature overview

2.1 A first QUD account for auch (‘also’)

Under a QUD account of focus, focus indicates alternatives which are distinct possible answers to a salient question under discussion (Roberts 2012: i.a.), cf. e.g., (3), where the focus accent is indicated using small caps.

(3) a. OTTO had a beer.
  b. { Otto had a beer, Paula had a beer, Quentin had a beer, …}
  c. QUD: Who had a beer?

This accounts for the intuition that (3a) can be used in contexts where the addressee knows (or considers expectable) that somebody had a beer, but does not know who, e.g., in answers to an overt question or in corrections of statements like Paula had a beer. When the placement of the focus accent changes, the alternatives and QUD change, too (4).

(4) a. Otto had a BEER.
  b. { Otto had a beer, Otto had a schnaps, Otto had a cocktail, … }
  c. QUD: What did Otto have?

Auch (‘also’, ‘too’) does not change the truth-conditions of the sentence, it merely introduces a presupposition. Unstressed auch is focus-sensitive: the presupposition contributed by auch changes when the location of the focus accent changes (5).1

    1. (5)
    1. a.
    1. Otto
    2. Otto
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. auch
    2. also
    1. ALTE
    2. old
    1. Bücher
    2. books
    1. gekauft.
    2. bought
    1. ‘Otto also bought OLD books.’
    2. PRESUPP ≈ Otto bought other kinds of books (e.g., new books).
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Otto
    2. Otto
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. auch
    2. also
    1. alte
    2. old
    1. BÜCHER
    2. books
    1. gekauft.
    2. bought
    1. ‘Otto also bought old BOOKS.’
    2. PRESUPP ≈ Otto bought other old things (e.g., old furniture).

Under a QUD account, additive particles associating with focus indicate that a previously answered question is re-opened in order to add a further answer, thereby marking the previous answer as partial (Beaver & Clark 2008; Jasinskaja & Zeevat 2009), see (6).

    1. (6)

In the following, such an account will be adopted for both auch and noch, and will be refined in order to account for the differences between the two particles.

2.2 Previous QUD accounts of additive noch

Additive noch is assumed to be very similar to auch: First, it merely contributes a presupposition and has no effect on the truth conditions. Second, it is focus-sensitive (7).2

    1. (7)
    1. a.
    1. Dann
    2. Then
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. Otto
    2. Otto
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. ALTE
    2. old
    1. Bücher
    2. books
    1. gekauft.
    2. bought
    1. ‘Otto bought OLD books in addition.’
    2. PRESUPP ≈ Otto bought other kinds of books (e.g., new books).
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Dann
    2. Then
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. Otto
    2. Otto
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. alte
    2. old
    1. BÜCHER
    2. books
    1. gekauft.
    2. bought
    1. ‘Otto bought old BOOKS in addition.’
    2. PRESUPP ≈ Otto bought other old things (e.g., old furniture).

Noch has a variety of uses, e.g., as a scale alignment particle corresponding to still in English (e.g. Löbner 1989; Krifka 2000; Ippolito 2007; Beck 2020). The basic reading of noch is temporal, indicating that an eventuality continues to hold at the reference time (8).

    1. (8)
    1. Imperfective reading
    1. Es
    2. it
    1. regnet
    2. rains
    1. noch.
    2. still
    1. ‘It is still raining.’
      1. Assertion: it is raining
      2. Presupposition: it rained before
      3. Possible implicature: it will stop raining soon

Other readings of noch involve different scales and different entities ranked on these scales, e.g. (9), where individuals are ranked on a scale of locations (a path).

    1. (9)
    1. Basel
    2. Basel
    1. liegt
    2. lies
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. in
    2. in
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Schweiz.
    2. Switzerland
    1. ‘Basel is still in Switzerland.’

Beck (2020) proposes the unified lexical entry in (10a) (see also Klein 2007; Beck 2016). Thereby, S is a salient scale, and x and x* are entities ranked on this scale (x* is salient). The semantic types of x, x* and P and the nature of S vary across readings.

(10) [[noch/still]] = λS.λx*.λx.λP⟨x,t⟩: x* ≺S x & P(x*). P(x)

The next sections discuss how this account has been adopted for additive noch.

2.2.1 Eckardt (2007)

Regine Eckardt (2007) adopts the account discussed above for additive noch, the scale S being the order of mention, and the entities ranked on the scale being answers to the QUD:

    1. (11)
    1. Otto
    2. Otto
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. SCHNAPS
    2. Schnaps
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk.
    1. ‘Otto also drank a SCHNAPS.’
      1. ASSERTION: Otto drank a schnaps
      2. PRESUPP.: there is an earlier-mentioned “positive” alternative
      3. IMPLICATURE: later-mentioned alternatives are “negative”

Eckardt reports two main differences between auch and noch: First, only noch gives rise to expectations about a following negative phase. Consider (12) (Eckardt 2007: p. 80): If the focus alternatives are contextually restricted to Tick, Trick and Track (Donald Duck’s nephews), (12a) is odd—according to Eckardt—because all answers are positive. (12b) is ideal because the host sentence of noch (Trick kann noch schwimmen) is followed by a negated sentence (Track kann nicht schwimmen).

    1. (12)
    1. (Tick kann schwimmen, und TRICK kann noch schwimmen, …/‘Huey can swim, and Dewey can noch swim…’)
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. #und
    2.   and
    1. TRACK
    2. Louie
    1. kann
    2. can
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. schwimmen.
    2. swim
    1.   ‘and Louie can ‘noch’ swim.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1.   aber
    2.   but
    1. Track
    2. Louie
    1. kann
    2. can
    1. nicht
    2. not
    1. schwimmen.
    2. swim
    1.   ‘but Louie can’t swim.’

Second, Eckardt notes that noch—in contrast to auch—requires a “fixed and stable” domain of alternatives. For example, (13) gets odd as soon as it becomes clear that the speaker is randomly listing even numbers (Eckardt 2007: p. 81).

    1. (13)
    1. (2 is an even number…)
    1. 4
    2. 4
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. gerade,
    2. even
    1. 6
    2. 6
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. gerade,
    2. even
    1. #78
    2. 78
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. gerade…
    2. even
    1. ‘4 is noch even, 6 is noch even, 78 is noch even…’

The first difference in (12) is due to the implicature involved with noch (11c). The second difference in (13) however needs to be accounted for independently. Eckardt suggests that auch indicates that a QUD is re-opened with respect to new alternatives, whereas noch indicates that a QUD is re-opened with respect to a subset of the previous alternatives. For example, the initial QUD in (13) might felicitously involve all numbers from 1–10, and each successive QUD then involves a subset of the alternatives in the preceding QUD (e.g., numbers from 1–10 excluding 2, numbers from 1–10 excluding {2,4}, etc.). As soon as it becomes clear that this domain is very large, possibly infinite, noch is infelicitous.

Eckardt’s proposal for noch is shown in (14), based on the definitions in (15) (Eckardt 2007: p. 87–89).

(14) a. Use of noch in questions: A question q in a QAD [‘Question Answer Discourse’] licenses noch iff
    (i) it is a remnant question
    (ii) it is dominated by a question Q such that there are assertions between Q and q, and all assertions between Q and q are positive answers to Q.
  b. Use of noch in assertions: An assertion u in a QAD licenses noch iff
    u is a positive answer to its dominating question q, and q licenses noch.
(15) a. Answerhood in a given context: An assertion S constitutes an answer to a question ⟨P,A⟩ in a given discourse context C iff for at least one aA, the augmented context C+[[S]] |= P(a) or C+[[S]] |= ¬P(a)
  b. Complete answer to question ⟨P,A⟩ in context C: An assertion S is a complete answer to ⟨P,A⟩ in C iff for all a in A, C+[[S]] |= P(a) or C+[[S]] |= ¬P(a)
  c. Partial answer: An assertion S is a partial answer to Q = ⟨P,A⟩ in C iff S is an answer, but not a complete answer to Q.
  d. Subquestion of a question Q in context C: A question Q’ is a subquestion of Q in context C iff a complete answer to Q’ in C is a partial answer to Q in C.
    Specifically, the following types of question-subquestion relation hold against the empty context:
    If ⟨P,A⟩ is a question and A’ ⊂ A, then ⟨P,A’⟩ is a subquestion of ⟨P,A⟩ against the empty context
    If Q is a Wh-question ⟨P,A⟩ and Q’ is a yes-no question for P about one a ∈ A: Q’ = ⟨λF.F (^P(a)), {λp.p, λp.¬p}⟩, then Q’ is a subquestion of Q in the empty context.
  e. Remnant question: A question R is the remnant question to a question Q in context C iff R is a subquestion to Q in the empty context, and a complete answer to R in context C is a complete answer to Q in C.
  f. Question Answer Discourse: An ordered binary tree represents a coherent QAD iff
    (i) Its root is a question
    (ii) No assertion dominates a question
    (iii) For all questions Q in a QAD with local context C: The daughters of Q are either
      - two partial questions that together are equivalent to Q or
      - an answer S plus the remnant question to Q in context C+[[S]]. (If the answer is complete, then the remnant question may be empty.)

Note first that questions are represented as structured meanings (von Stechow 1990), i.e., as a pair ⟨P,A⟩, whereby A is a set of alternatives, and P a property. For example, the meaning of Who swam? is represented as ⟨λx. Swam(x), HUMAN ∩ C⟩, whereby C contextually restricts the domain of individuals under consideration. Second, note that discourse trees are assumed to be binary in Eckardt’s account, i.e., in contrast to the proposal sketched in §2.1 above, where re-opened questions are sister questions as in (16), they are often subquestions in Eckardt’s account (17).

    1. (16)
    1. (17)

Under Eckardt’s account, noch thus differs from auch in that (i) it involves a restricted and fixed domain of focus alternatives, modelled via the restriction that noch-answers can only answer a remnant question, and (ii) in that it indicates a following negative phase.

2.2.2 Umbach (2012)

Carla Umbach adopts Eckardt’s QUD account, but argues that the domain of alternatives is extended with noch, too.3 Umbach argues that this can be seen in questions (Umbach 2012: p. 1847). In wh-questions, noch is the standard additive particle, i.e., it involves new, previously unconsidered alternatives, whereas auch is marked: it suggests that the questioner already knows the answer. For example, in (18) (adapted from Umbach 2012: p. 1845), the mother, who doesn’t know what happened, can ask the neutral question (18a), but not (18b), because the latter is a request for a specific answer.

    1. (18)
    1. (Little Lisa tells her mother what happened when she visited the zoo with Auntie.)
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. Mother:
    1. Und
    2. and
    1. was
    2. what
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. im
    2. in.the
    1. Zoo
    2. zoo
    1. NOCH
    2. still
    1. passiert?
    2. happened
    1. ‘What else happened at the zoo?’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Auntie/# Mother:
    1. Und
    2. and
    1. was
    2. what
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. im
    2. in.the
    1. Zoo
    2. zoo
    1. AUCH
    2. also
    1. passiert?
    2. happened
    1. ‘What happened at the zoo, too?’

Umbach proposes that both auch and noch indicate that a QUD is re-opened with respect to an extended domain of alternatives. They differ in that alternatives are ordered (by time of mention) with noch.

According to Umbach, this causes the following contrast: with dannnoch, the events can be ordered by time of mention (“discourse time”) (19a), whereas with dannauch the order of the two events is necessarily aligned with “real time” (19b) (Umbach 2012: p. 1844).

    1. (19)
    1. (Otto had a beer.)
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. Dann
    2. then
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. SCHNAPS
    2. schnaps
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. (no particular order)
    2.  
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Dann
    2. then
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. auch
    2. also
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. SCHNAPS
    2. schnaps
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. (beer ≺ schnaps)
    2.  
    1. ‘Then he drank a schnaps in addition.’

Umbach proposes that dann is ambiguous (discourse time dann (19a) vs.real time dann (19b)). According to Umbach, the fact that (19a) allows for the discourse time interpretation has to do with the alternatives, in the case of noch, being ordered by discourse time. In fact, noch is most felicitous with (discourse time) dann and similar elements (Umbach 2012: p. 1851). Umbach writes that discourse time dann facilitates the additive reading because it indicates that the answers are disjoint.

Umbach also provides (20) as evidence for the claim that noch, but not auch, involves ordered alternatives. (20) is felicitous with accented noch with the interpretation of another.

    1. (20)
    1. (Otto had a schnaps. And you won’t believe it:)
    1. Er
    2. he
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. NOCH
    2. still
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. Schnaps
    2. schnaps
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. (#auch)
    2.  
    1. ‘He had another schnaps.’/‘# He had a schnaps, too’

Umbach proposes that stressed NOCH in (20) has the same meaning as unstressed noch. Umbach suggests that einen Schnaps is focused (but deaccented because it is given), and proposes that noch can associate with deaccented foci because the alternatives can be individuated due to their order. In the case of auch, the alternatives are not ordered, and thus auch cannot associate with Schnaps in (20).

Umbach (2012: p. 1852) proposes the following meaning for additive noch (also relying on structured meanings (von Stechow 1990), whereby F is the focused constituent, B is a predicate corresponding to the background, and Alt(F) are the focus alternatives):

(21) noch (⟨B,F⟩) iff ⟨B,F⟩
  where Alt(F) is ordered such that the order is aligned with the order of mentioning <m on the subset of mentioned alternatives Altm(F), and F is maximal in Altm(F);
  presupposing that ∃x ∈ Altm(F) such that x ≠ F, x <m F, and ⟨B,x⟩

The only difference to auch is that the alternatives are ordered in the case of noch. Concerning the behavior of auch and noch in questions (18), Umbach argues that this is due to AUCH associating with contrastive topics. Since topics are referential, this enforces a referential reading of the wh-element.

Umbach proposes the following QUD account (Umbach 2012: p. 1861), where B is a property corresponding to the background and D its domain, a set of alternatives which are possible arguments for B.4 Intuitively, D is the set of elements that can replace the wh-element in the corresponding answer.

(22) a. unstressed auch in questions indicates that the question is an extension question
  b. unstressed auch in answers addresses an extension question.
(23) a. noch in questions indicates that the question is a continuation question;
  b. noch in answers addresses a continuation question
(24) a. A question q0 = ⟨B0, D0⟩ is an extension question with respect to a preceding question q–1 = ⟨B–1, D–1⟩ iff
    (i) B0=B–1 (ii) D0 ∩ D–1= ∅ (iii) DS = D–1 ∪ D0 is a superordinate domain
  b. A question q0 = ⟨B0, D0⟩ is an extension question with respect to a preceding assertion a–1 = ⟨B–1, F⟩, Alt(F)–1 iff
    (i) B0=B–1 (ii) D0 ∩ Alt(F)–1= ∅ (i) DS = Alt(F)–1∪ D0 is a superordinate domain
    The definitions are adapted to polarity questions q = ⟨λF.F(P(a)), {λp.p, λp.¬p}⟩ by assigning B:=P and D:= {a}
(25) A question q0 = ⟨B0, D0⟩ is a continuation question iff it is an extension question such that D0 is ordered. Combination of D0 and D–1 or Alt(F)–1 has to be order preserving.

In Umbach’s account, a wh-question is thus assumed to be re-opened with respect to a different domain of alternatives (26). This holds for both auch and noch.

    1. (26)

Auch and noch differ in that noch involves a subset of mentioned alternatives, ordered by time of mentioning, and triggers the presupposition that there is a prementioned alternative.

2.2.3 Grubic (2018)

Grubic (2018) adopts Eckardt’s and Umbach’s account of (unstressed) auch as involving an extended domain of alternatives, but proposes an account according to which topic situations play a role for the interpretation of noch. (Austinian) topic situations are the situations that the respective sentences are about (Austin 1950; Kratzer 2020). Situations are parts of worlds. Propositions are assumed to be functions from situations to truth values. The truth of a proposition is evaluated with respect to its topic situation s0, and (usually) not the whole world w0. Grubic (2018) demonstrates this using (27) (a version of an example from Barwise & Etchemendy 1987, see Kratzer 2020). The idea that (27) is perceived to be false even though Claire does have the three of clubs in the evaluation world can be captured by assuming that (27) is evaluated with respect to a topic situation containing only Game 1, but not Game 2.

(27) (Emily is playing a card game (Game 1), and somewhere else, Claire is playing cards (Game 2). Both have the three of clubs.) Someone, watching game 1, mistakes Emily for Claire and says:
  Claire has the three of clubs.

Declarative utterances inherit their topic situation from their immediate QUD (Kratzer 2020), whereas the topic situation of a QUD is a subsituation of the topic situation of its immediate superquestion (Schwarz 2009: p. 166). Tense, as well as sentence-initial temporal or locative (so-called frame-setting) adverbials can provide further information about the topic situation (Maienborn 2001; Klein 2008; Frazier & Clifton 2018; Kratzer 2020). Following Schwarz (2009: p. 93–94), topic situations are assumed to be syntactically represented as situation variables high in the clause (e.g., in TP or CP), which are arguments to an operator TOPIC. This operator ensures that the proposition is evaluated with respect to the topic situation: the proposition is a property of counterparts of the topic situation, i.e. of “the same” situation in different worlds (Lewis 1986).

    1. (28)
(29) [[TOPIC]] = λp.λs′.λs. s ≈ s′ & p(s)
  where ‘≈’ is the counterpart relation

Grubic (2018) follows Eckardt (2007) and Umbach (2012) in the assumption that auch indicates that a QUD is re-opened to include further, hitherto ignored alternatives (30).5 Noch, in contrast, indicates that a QUD is re-opened with respect to a different topic situation (31)–(32). Thus, in contrast to Eckardt (2007) and Umbach (2012), Grubic (2018) does not assume that noch poses any restrictions on the domain of alternatives in the QUD.

(30) unstressed auch in answers addresses an extension question;
  unstressed auch in questions indicates that the question is an extension question.
  (from Umbach 2012: p. 1861, see (22) above)
(31) noch in answers addresses a shifted question;
  noch in questions indicates that the question is shifted.
(32) A question Q=⟨B,D⟩ about s is a shifted question with respect to a preceding question Q′ = ⟨B′,D′⟩ about s′ iff (i) B=B′, (ii) s ≠ s′

The trees in (33)–(34) show the assumed QUD hierarchies for unstressed auch and noch.6

    1. (33)
    1. (34)

Grubic argues that this account can explain Umbach’s data discussed in §2.2.2.7 First, the reason why noch is most felicitous with e.g. dann (‘then’, (35)) is that dann is a topic-situation shifter.

(35) (Otto had a beer.)
  a. Dann hat er noch/auch einen SCHNAPS getrunken.
    ‘Then he also drank a schnaps.’
  b. Er hat auch/??noch einen SCHNAPS getrunken.
    (intended:) ‘He also drank a schnaps.’

Second, the use of auch indicates that relevant alternatives were neglected in a preceding answer. When used in a question, it thus indicates that the addressee forgot or neglected relevant alternatives—thus accounting for its markedness (36).

(36) (Little Lisa tells her mother what happened when she visited the zoo with Auntie.)
  a. Mother: Und was ist im Zoo NOCH passiert?
    ‘What else happened at the zoo?’
  b. Auntie: Und was ist im Zoo AUCH passiert?
    ‘What happened at the zoo, too?’ (# mother)

Third, following Umbach (2012), Grubic (2018) adopted the idea that stressed NOCH associates with Schnaps in (37). Grubic (2018) proposed that noch only requires a shift in topic situation—the domain of focus alternatives (of e.g., Schnaps) can in principle be the same as in the preceding answer, i.e., a preceding answer can be provided again without being uninformative (since it is about a different topic situation).

(37) (Otto had a schnaps. And you won’t believe it:)
  Er hat NOCH einen Schnaps getrunken.(#auch)
  ‘He had another schnaps.’/‘# He had a schnaps, too.’

Finally, Grubic (2018)’s account correctly predicts that auch and noch can co-occur (38). Auch requires an extended domain of alternatives (compatible with a shift in topic situation). Noch requires a topic situation shift (compatible with an extended domain of alternatives).8

    1. (38)
    1. (Otto hat ein Bier getrunken)
    1. Otto
    2. Otto
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. auch
    2. also
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. SCHNAPS
    2. schnaps
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. ‘Otto also drank a schnaps.’
    2. (PRESUPP: Otto drank something else (e.g., a beer))

To sum up, the previous QUD accounts for additive noch agree that unstressed auch indicates that the domain of considered alternative answers to the QUD is extended. The proposals differ for additive noch: According to Eckardt (2007), noch in an answer indicates that its QUD involves a subset of the antecedent QUD’s domain of alternatives. According to Umbach (2012) and Grubic (2018), the domain of alternatives is extended with noch, too. Umbach (2012) argues that with noch, the alternatives are ordered by time of mention. Grubic (2018) proposes that the QUD of the noch sentence involves a different topic situation than the antecedent QUD (whereas auch usually—but not necessarily—involves the same topic situation).

2.3 A prediction

In the preceding sections, examples such as (39) were discussed. Grubic (2018) suggested that although, superficially, this looks like one coherent situation, the use of dann and noch indicates that the second sentence is about a shifted situation.

    1. (39)
    1. (Otto had a beer.)
    1. Dann
    2. then
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. SCHNAPS
    2. schnaps
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. ‘And he also drank a schnaps.’

This predicts that when there is a clear shift to a temporally distinct topic situation, for example one that takes place much later than the first situation, the difference between auch and noch should be more clearly visible. One clear case of overt topic situation shift are initial temporal or locative adverbials (40) (Frazier & Clifton 2018).

(40) Topic Situation Hypothesis: Initial temporal and locative PPs introduce Topic Situations. By default, following material is included in the Topic Situation until a new Topic Situation, or incompatible information, is encountered.

Given this assumption, Grubic’s (2018) account predicts for noch in (41) that the first sentence can be the required antecedent, since noch merely requires a preceding answer to the same QUD about a different topic situation.

    1. (41)
    1. (Five years ago, Bertha walked the first eleven stages of the Way of St. James.)
    1. Letztes
    2. last
    1. Jahr
    2. year
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. sie
    2. she
    1. auch/noch
    2. also/still
    1. die
    2. the
    1. letzten
    2. last
    1. 21
    2. 21
    1. Etappen
    2. stages
    1. gelaufen.
    2. walked
    1. ‘Last year, she also/additionally walked the last 21 stages.’

The main accent lies on the object (‘the last 21 stages’), leading to a QUD such as How many stages did she walk?. There is an initial temporal expression (‘last year’) indicating that the topic situation is changed with respect to the antecedent (‘five years ago’). This account thus predicts the QUD hierarchy in (43) for noch, involving the two situations in (42). Noch in (43) presupposes a previous answer to the question How many stages did Bertha walk? about a different topic situation than S2. This previous answer is provided (She walked stages 1–11 in S1). Thus, the presupposition is satisfied in this context, and it is predicted that no accommodation takes place.

(42) S1: Five years ago
  S2: Last year
    1. (43)

Since, according to Grubic (2018), auch requires a change in the domain of alternatives in the QUD, but does not impose any requirements with respect to the topic situation, this interpretation (without accommodation) is predicted to be possible for auch, too.

In addition, a second possible interpretation is predicted for auch but not for noch. It was observed for also in English that accommodation takes place in contexts with such shifted topic situations: Kim (2012; 2015) reports that in examples like (44)—where arguably the topic situation is shifted via a contrastive topic—participants accommodate a presupposition.

(44) (Mark has some pears and some oranges.)
  Jane also has some APPLES.
  (accommodated: Jane has some pears and some oranges)

If unstressed auch patterns like also in this respect, it is expected that participants can accommodate a presupposition about the new topic situation S2 in (41), namely that Bertha walked stages 1–11 again, in addition to stages 12–32.9

    1. (45)

Grubic’s account thus predicts a difference between auch and noch with respect to their accommodation behavior. We believe that Eckardt (2007) and Umbach (2012) do not make such predictions. Under both accounts, auch/noch require a previous answer to the question How many stages did Bertha walk last year?, therefore the preceding overt sentence does not satisfy the presupposition of auch/noch—the no-accommodation reading isn’t possible. Eckardt does not discuss accommodation—we thus tentatively propose that Eckardt’s account would predict the same behavior for auch and noch. Umbach states that neither additive noch (Umbach 2012) nor auch (Umbach 2009) allow for accommodation. This leads to the predictions in Table 1 for examples like (41).

Table 1

Predicted possible readings for examples with overt topic situation shift.

auch noch
accomm. no accomm. accomm. no accomm.
Eckardt 2007 ✓(?) ✓(?)
Umbach 2012
Grubic 2018

2.4 Previous experimental work

The prediction discussed above was put to a first test in a pilot study.10

The stimuli were presented auditorily. They consisted of a context and a target sentence with auch/noch, containing different temporal PPs similar to (41) above. 32 participants saw eight items in both conditions and provided felicity ratings and answers to questions indicating whether accommodation took place. Presupposition accommodation was found in 72% of auch sentences and 39% of noch sentences. This difference was significant according to a logistic regression model (z = 8.28, p < 0.001). The continuation with noch was degraded (3.1 on a 1–5 scale) in comparison to auch (4.1); this difference was also significant according to a cumulative link model (z = 6.17, p < 0.001). The results suggest that auch and noch may indeed differ with respect to accommodation.

The test items in these pilot experiments were deliberately set up in a way that made accommodation very plausible. The motivation for this was to facilitate accommodation with auch, since the presupposition of auch is usually assumed to be hard to accommodate (Kripke 2009). We hypothesize that this was the reason why noch was deemed less acceptable by the participants.

This opens up an interesting direction for extending the experiment: if we manipulate how plausible the readings with/without accommodation are, we would expect this to affect the felicity and interpretation of sentences with auch/noch in very specific ways, if Grubic’s (2018) account is correct. In our experiment reported in §3, we thus not only vary the trigger (within items) but also systematically vary (between items) whether accommodation is plausible or not, i.e., whether it is likely, given our world knowledge, that the eventuality is repeated. Section §3.1 discusses a pre-experiment in which we tested our test items for plausibility. Section §3.2 then reports our main experiment.

3 Our experiment

3.1 Plausibility pre-test

3.1.1 Motivation

Our main experiment required three kinds of items: (i) ones in which repetition and non-repetition of an action is equally likely, (ii) ones in which only repetition is likely, and (iii) ones in which repetition is unlikely. In order to make sure that all materials satisfied this requirement, we conducted a pre-experiment testing for plausibility of the repetition.

3.1.2 Participants and procedure

Twenty native speakers of German, recruited and paid via Prolific (prolific.co), took part in the pre-test. The stimuli were presented in written form using the online questionnaire software L-Rex (Starschenko & Wierzba 2020).

On each page, a context and a target sentence was shown. A clarification sentence followed the target sentence, making as clear as possible whether the event was repeated or not. The participants were instructed to judge whether the described continuation is logically possible, and if so, whether it is plausible. After picking an answer (“possible and plausible”, “possible but implausible”, “impossible”), there was the option of providing a comment.

Each participant rated 48 stimuli. On average, completing the questionnaire took 25 minutes.

3.1.3 Design and materials

We constructed 36 contexts in total. Each of them was paired with a target sentence in which the action was either (a) continued or (b) repeated.

We expected the contexts to fall into three equal groups (12 contexts per group), which we will refer to as ±REP, +REP, and –REP. We intended to use the (±REP) group as a baseline—we expected both continuations to be judged as possible and plausible. As for the +REP contexts, we expected them to be judged as implausible or impossible with continuation (a) (continued action) and possible and plausible with continuation (b) (repeated action). For the –REP contexts, we expected the opposite: possible and plausible with continuation (a) (continued action), and implausible or impossible with continuation (b). The expectations are summarized in Table 2.11

Table 2

Plausibility experiment: predicted answer proportions (continuation types: cont. = continued action, rep. = repeated action).

±REP +REP REP
cont. rep. cont. rep. cont. rep.
possible and plausible high high low high high low
implausible/impossible low low high low low high

Examples for each kind of context are shown below (as in the actual experimental stimuli, the target sentence is marked by italics, and crucial parts are highlighted by boldface).12 The first sentence described an activity. The second sentence stated that the activity was discontinued, but suggested that the agent would have liked to continue. This was included in order to increase the plausibility of returning to this activity at a later point. The third sentence was the test sentence. Condition (a) always involved a complement anaphoric expression (e.g., letzte ‘last’); the distribution of these expressions was balanced. We included them anticipating that we were going to add noch/auch to the sentences in the main experiment, and we felt that they enhance the felicity of noch (see §4 for discussion).

(46) ±REP Five years ago, Bertha walked the first eleven stages of the Way of St. James. Then she unfortunately had to discontinue her pilgrimage because of an injury.
  a. Last year, she walked the last 21 stages of the Way of St. James.
    (i.e., only the part of the way that she didn’t walk five years ago).
  b. Last year, she walked all 32 stages of the Way of St. James.
    (i.e., including the part of the way that she walked five years ago).
(47) +REP: Yesterday on her way to work, Lara rode her bike for the first 2km. For the last 3km she unfortunately had to push her bike because her bike broke down.
  a. Today on her way to work she rode her bike for the last 3km.
    (i.e., only the part of the way that she didn’t cycle yesterday).
  b. Today on her way to work, she rode her bike for the whole 5km.
    (i.e., including the way that she cycled yesterday).
(48) REP During the summer holidays, Quentin drank five wine bottles from his supply. He saved two for later.
  a. During the winter holidays, he drank the last two wine bottles from his supply.
    (i.e., only the bottles that he didn’t drink in the summer holidays).
  b. During the winter holidays, he drank all seven wine bottles from his supply.
    (i.e., including the bottles that he had drunk in the summer holidays).

The items were distributed using a Latin-Square design (two lists with 36 items each) and randomized. Since we expected a large majority of “possible and plausible”-answers (for items of type (46), (47b), and (48a) above), we added twelve filler items for which we expected “possible but implausible” or “impossible” answers in order to achieve a more balanced distribution of expected responses.

Our goal was to identify the contexts with the clearest distribution of plausibility ratings per group while eliminating potentially problematic ones. We aimed to select eight items per group to be used in the main experiment.

3.1.4 Results

The results for all 36 items are summarized in Table 3.13 Based on a by-item inspection of the data, we removed those four items from each group that corresponded least to our expectations. Table 4 shows the results for the remaining 24 items that we selected to be used in the main experiment.

Table 3

Results of the plausibility pre-test: proportion of answer types per context group and continuation type (all 36 items).

±REP +REP REP
cont. rep. cont. rep. cont. rep.
possible and plausible 68% 90% 23% 87% 89% 8%
possible but implausible 28% 9% 60% 11% 4% 10%
impossible 3% 1% 18% 3% 7% 83%
Table 4

Results of the plausibility pre-test: proportion of answer types per context group and continuation type (selected 24 items, to be used in the main experiment).

±REP +REP REP
cont. rep. cont. rep. cont. rep.
possible and plausible 79% 86% 15% 89% 96% 3%
possible but implausible 20% 14% 70% 10% 4% 5%
impossible 1% 0% 15% 1% 0% 93%

For statistical analysis of the selected items, the answer types “possible but implausible” and “impossible” were collapsed to a single category. The factor context group was treatment-coded with ±REP as the baseline. Continuation type was sum-coded.

According to a logistic regression model, there was no significant simple effect of continuation type (continued vs. repeated action) within the ±REP baseline (z = –0.52, p = 0.60).14 A significant interaction between continuation type and context group was found for both +REP (z = 6.96, p < 0.001) and –REP (z = –5.44, p < 0.001): the difference between continued and repeated action was larger for these two groups in comparison to the baseline. As expected, the interactions go in opposite directions: in the +REP, the proportion of “possible and plausible” answers was smaller with continued actions, whereas in the –REP group, it was smaller with repeated actions.

3.1.5 Discussion

Based on the pre-test, we were able to select three groups of contexts that clearly differ with respect to how plausible it is that the same action is repeated or continued. Thus, we have robust empirical support for the validity of the item groups that will be used in the main experiment.

3.2 Main experiment

3.2.1 Motivation

The goal of the main experiment is to test the predictions made by Grubic’s (2018) account concerning the accommodation behavior of auch and noch. In the main experiment, we combine the contexts from the pre-test with a sentence containing one of the particles:

(49) Five years ago, Bertha walked the first eleven stages of the Way of St. James. Last year, she walked auch/noch the last 21 stages.

Recall that Grubic predicts that accommodation of Last year, Bertha walked the first eleven stages is possible (but not necessary) for auch, but not possible for noch, since the latter requires a previous answer about a different topic situation.

Based on the results of the pre-test, we can now systematically manipulate how plausible accommodation is. If, as predicted, both interpretations are indeed possible for auch in these kinds of examples, then the conditions including auch should always be acceptable; whether speakers accommodate should merely depend on plausibility. If accommodation is indeed excluded in the case of noch, then the conditions including noch should be less acceptable when accommodation is the only plausible interpretation.

This design remedies a potential problem of the pilot experiment, namely that accommodation was always highly plausible, potentially introducing a bias for one of the interpretations.

3.2.2 Participants and procedure

The experiment, including the planned analysis, was pre-registered at the Open Science Foundation (https://osf.io/r97kc/) prior to data collection. Our materials and data can also be found there.

Twenty-four native speakers of German, recruited and paid via Prolific, took part in the experiment. Participants who participated in the plausibility pre-test could not participate in the main experiment. The experiment was again set up as a web-based questionnaire.

Participants were instructed to use headphones. On each page, they read a context that was presented in written form and then clicked on a play button to listen to the target sentence (recorded by the second author of the paper), which formed a continuation of the text. Since additive particles are focus-sensitive, auditory stimuli were used in order to ensure the correct interpretation. The nuclear accent was always on the constituent that the particle associated with. It was possible to listen to the stimulus several times.

Below, two questions were presented. The first question concerned the felicity of the target sentence as a continuation of the text, on a scale from 1 (“very bad, does not make sense in this context”) to 5 (“very good, makes sense in this context”). The second one was a content question. This was a forced-choice task: two answers were provided and the participants had to choose one.

The stimuli were presented in randomized order. Each participant rated 48 stimuli (24 critical items and 24 fillers). On average, completing the questionnaire took 32 minutes.

3.2.3 Design and materials

The main experiment had a 3 × 2 design. The first (between-items) factor that we manipulated was context type (±REP, +REP, –REP). The second factor (within-items) was particle (auch vs. noch).

We used 24 items selected based on the results of the pre-test. In addition, two of the selected contexts with the lowest proportion of expected answers were slightly adapted in order to enhance the desired interpretation. Furthermore, because selecting 24/32 items from the pre-test changed the distribution of the different complement anaphoric expressions (letzte ‘last’, andere ‘other’, restliche/übrige ‘remaining’), we also adjusted this so that the distribution was balanced again. A list of items is provided in Appendix B.

As described above, the contexts used in the pre-test were paired with target sentences containing either auch or noch, as in (50).

    1. (50)
    1. Five years ago, Bertha walked the first eleven stages of the Way of St. James. Then she unfortunately had to discontinue her pilgrimage because of an injury.
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. Letztes
    2. last
    1. Jahr
    2. year
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. sie
    2. she
    1. auch
    2. also
    1. die
    2. the
    1. letzten
    2. last
    1. 21
    2. 21
    1. Etappen
    2. stages
    1. des
    2. of.the
    1. Jakobswegs
    2. James.way
    1. gelaufen.
    2. walked
    1. ‘Last year, she also walked the last 21 stages of the Way of St. James.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Letztes
    2. last
    1. Jahr
    2. year
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. sie
    2. she
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. die
    2. the
    1. letzten
    2. last
    1. 21
    2. 21
    1. Etappen
    2. stages
    1. des
    2. of.the
    1. Jakobswegs
    2. James.way
    1. gelaufen.
    2. walked
    1. ‘Last year, she walked the last 21 stages of the Way of St. James in addition.’

The corresponding content question is shown in (51). Answer (51a) indicates that accommodation has taken place (i.e., it is accommodated that the action described in the context was repeated). Answer (51b) indicates no accommodation (i.e., the target sentence is interpreted as a continuation, without repetition of the first part). In the question, the time adverbial was highlighted, based on our impression during test trials that this facilitated understanding that the question was about the situation described by the target sentence.

(51) How many stages of the Way of St. James did Bertha walk **last year**?
  a. All 32 stages.
  b. Only the last 21 stages.

The items were distributed using a Latin Square design (two lists with 24 items each). We added 24 filler items, consisting of sentences with other presuppositional elements, namely wieder/nochmal ‘again’ and nur ‘only’. Half of the filler items were predicted to be felicitous, half infelicitous (Appendix C discusses the results for the filler items).

We used four of the filler items as controls to check whether participants were paying attention and responding to the task in the intended way. We chose fillers in which the expected response did not depend on accommodation, but only required to pay close attention to the context and the response options. An example is shown in (52).

(52) When he went to the ice-cream parlor yesterday, Julian ate two scoops of ice cream. After that, he was unfortunately too full to eat dinner.
  When he went to the ice-cream parlor today, he only ate one scoop of ice cream.

The context question was either ‘How many scoops of ice cream did Julian eat **today**?’ or ‘…**yesterday**?’; the answer options were “one scoop” and “two scoops”. We excluded participants from the analysis who gave less than 3/4 expected answers in these controls.15

3.2.4 Hypotheses

If Grubic’s (2018) assumptions about auch and noch are correct, we would expect to find the following patterns:

(53) Felicity hypothesis:
  Noch should be less felicitous in contexts in which only the interpretation with accommodation is plausible (+REP) in comparison to the baseline (±REP), whereas auch is expected to be felicitous in both.

This hypothesis predicts an interaction between particle and context type with respect to felicity ratings: the felicity difference between the two particles should be larger in +REP than in the ±REP baseline.

(54) Accommodation hypothesis:
  There should be less accommodation for auch in contexts in which only the interpretation without accommodation is plausible (–REP) than in the baseline context (±REP); for noch, the accommodation rate is expected to be low in both.

This hypothesis predicts an interaction between particle and context type with respect to the responses to the content question: the difference in accommodation rate between the two particles should be smaller in –REP than in the ±REP baseline.

More precisely, the accommodation hypothesis should be stated as an implication, because the account does not explicitly predict the reading without accommodation to be impossible with auch in the baseline context: if there is a difference in accommodation rate between the two particles in the baseline, we expect it to decrease in the context where this reading is implausible.

In Tables 5 and 6, the crucial predictions of the felicity and accommodation hypotheses are highlighted in boldface. As for the other cells in the table of predicted ratings, no difference is expected between –REP and the ±REP baseline: when only the interpretation without accommodation is plausible, both particles should be acceptable. As for the other cells in the table of predicted responses, Grubic (2018) predicts that the accommodation rate is high for auch in +REP examples, but does not make predictions for noch. This would depend on what participants choose to do when noch requires an interpretation of the test sentence that does not match the provided context (see §3.2.7 for discussion).

Table 5

Predictions of Grubic’s (2018) account for the main experiment: ratings.

Predicted ratings:
auch noch
±REP high high
+REP high low
REP high high
Table 6

Predictions of Grubic’s (2018) account for the main experiment: proportion of responses indicating accommodation.

Predicted responses:
auch noch
±REP high low
+REP high (?)
REP low low

3.2.5 Results

The results are summarized in Tables 7, 8 and Figures 1, 2.

Table 7

Results of the experiment: median and mean (standard deviation in parentheses) of the felicity ratings.

Ratings:
auch noch
median mean (SD) median mean (SD)
±REP 5 4.5 (1.0) 5 4.6 (0.7)
+REP 5 4.5 (0.7) 4 3.9 (0.6)
REP 5 4.7 (0.8) 5 4.8 (1.2)
Table 8

Results of the experiment: proportion of answers indicating accommodation.

Responses:
auch noch
±REP 40% 14%
+REP 89% 75%
REP 5% 7%
Figure 1
Figure 1

Felicity rating results of the main experiment: proportion of each rating category on a 1–5 scale.

Figure 2
Figure 2

Proportion of responses indicating accommodation in the main experiment.

The data of one participant were excluded from the analysis based on the exclusion criterion defined above.

For statistical analysis, the factor context group was treatment-coded with ±REP as the baseline. The factor particle (auch/noch) was sum-coded.

We will first present the analysis for the felicity ratings. According to a cumulative link model, the factor particle did not have a significant simple effect on the felicity ratings in the ±REP baseline (z = –0.11, p = 0.91): auch and noch were similarly acceptable. A significant main effect of context type was found for +REP (z = –3.32, p < 0.001): the ratings were lower than in the baseline. This effect was qualified by a significant interaction with particle (z = 3.23, p = 0.001): the decrease was larger for noch than for auch. For –REP, a significant main effect was found (z = 2.20, p = 0.03) in that the ratings were higher than in the baseline, but no significant interaction with particle was found (z = –0.87, p = 0.38).

As for the responses to the content question, there was a significant simple effect of particle on the responses in the ±REP baseline (z = 4.00, p < 0.001): there was a higher proportion of answers indicating accommodation for auch than for noch. There was also a significant main effect of context type for both +REP (z = 5.93, p < 0.001) and –REP (z = –2.85, p = 0.004): for the former, the proportion of answers indicating accommodation was higher than in the baseline; for the latter, it was lower than in the baseline. No significant interaction between particle and context type was found when comparing +REP to the baseline (z = –0.63, p = 0.53) (i.e., a similar difference between auch and noch was found in these context types), whereas the interaction was significant for –REP (z = –2.43, p = 0.02): the difference between the two particles was less pronounced in this context type.

3.2.6 Discussion

The prediction of the felicity hypothesis was borne out: noch was indeed perceived as less felicitous in the contexts in which only the interpretation with accommodation is plausible (+REP) in comparison to the baseline.

The prediction of the accommodation hypothesis was also borne out: an asymmetry with respect to the context question (indicating whether accommodation took place or not) was found between auch and noch in the baseline contexts, in which both readings are equally plausible; this asymmetry was less pronounced in the (–REP) contexts, where both particles showed a low accommodation rate.

Our results are thus compatible with Grubic’s (2018) account according to which auch, but not noch, allows for accommodation when a QUD is re-opened with respect to a new topic situation.

Our predictions were formulated in terms of the relative acceptability/accommodation rate when comparing auch and noch. With respect to the absolute values, note first that the accommodation rate for auch in the ±REP baseline is lower in comparison to the previous experiments reported by Kim (2012; 2015), but since both interpretations are plausible in the baseline, it is arguably not surprising that the reading that does not require accommodation is the preferred one. Second, and more surprisingly, note that noch is not completely infelicitous when the interpretation without accommodation is implausible, but only slightly degraded. We will discuss possible reasons in the following section.

3.2.7 Post-hoc analyses

In this section, we consider the following possible participant response strategies to the noch/+REP condition. Participants of type (1), (2b) and/or (2c) might all have contributed to the unexpectedly high ratings.

  1. NO-DIFFERENCE: There might be a subgroup of participants for whom the proposed situation-shifting property is not a necessary meaning component of noch, contra Grubic (2018). These participants interpret auch and noch the same.16

  2. DIFFERENCE: Participants for whom situation-shift is a necessary component of noch (in line with Grubic (2018)) could still have reacted in different ways:

    • (2a) LOWER-RATINGS: They might have perceived a clash between the particle and the context and chosen to lower their rating (the reaction expected by us).

    • (2b) IGNORE-CONTEXT: They might not have perceived the contextual bias towards accommodation as strong enough to affect their rating.

    • (2c) IGNORE-PARTICLE: They might have perceived a clash between the particle and the context, but chosen to resolve it by ignoring the particle.17

To test these hypotheses, we conducted post-hoc analyses of our data. We first divided the participants into two groups: those who showed the expected low rating in the noch/+REP condition and those who did not. We arbitrarily chose to make the split between participants with a median rating of 4 or lower (‘low felicity rating’, eleven participants) and all others (‘high felicity ratings’, twelve participants). We inspected the data of the latter to see whether their unexpectedly high rating came about due to assumption (1), (2b), or (2c).

If (1) holds, then we would expect to also find a high accommodation rate in the crucial noch/+REP condition and a very similar response pattern for auch and noch across all conditions. We thus divided the ‘high felicity ratings’ group further based on the accommodation rate in the noch/+REP condition (threshold: <75% vs. ≥75%). For eight participants, a high accommodation rate was found. For these participants, we indeed find very similar overall patterns for auch and noch, as shown in Figure 3: across all contexts, the accommodation rate for the two particles is almost identical (auch: 48%, noch: 46%), whereas the other participants show a much clearer overall distinction (auch: 43%, noch: 24%). This supports assumption (1) above.

Figure 3
Figure 3

Responses of the subgroup of speakers with a high acceptability rating (median > 4) and high accommodation rate (≥75%) in the noch/+REP condition: overall similar behavior of auch and noch, as predicted by NO-DIFFERENCE.

To check hypotheses (2b) and (2c) for the remaining three participants, we again looked at their responses in the other conditions. If (2b) holds, we would expect a weak effect of the contextual manipulation overall (especially in contexts ±REP vs. +REP; context –REP should be more difficult to ignore as the reading with accommodation often involved a logically impossible situation in this case). If (2c) holds, a strong effect of context is expected. The post-hoc inspection of the data (see Figure 4) suggests that the responses of this group of participants were generally affected less by the context (±REP baseline: 42% of accommodation, +REP: 63%, averaging over the two particles) than the other participants (±REP: 25%, +REP: 85%), which tentatively supports (2b).18

Figure 4
Figure 4

Responses of the subgroup of speakers with a high acceptability rating (median > 4) and low accommodation rate (<75%) in the noch/+REP condition: similar pattern in ±REP and +REP context, as predicted by IGNORE-CONTEXT.

Taken together, the post-hoc analyses suggest that the unexpectedly high results in the noch/+REP condition has multiple sources: (i) inter-speaker variation and (ii) different response strategies to the experimental task. There indeed is a subgroup of participants who did not differentiate between auch and noch for the purpose of our experiment. The majority of participants did differentiate them, but for some of them, the clash between the contextual bias and the meaning of the particle did not result in a strong felicity decrease. In the following, we will focus on the speakers that do make a distinction between auch and noch, with the aim of modeling the crucial differences between the particles in the grammar of the majority of the speakers of German.

4 General discussion and analysis

The results of our experiment are compatible with the predictions of Grubic’s (2018) account, repeated here as Table 9: noch is less felicitous in contexts favoring accommodation about the same topic situation, in line with the assumption that it requires a topic situation shift. Auch allows for accommodation or non-accommodation, depending on the context, in line with the assumption that it does not require a topic situation shift.

Table 9

Predicted possible readings for examples with overt topic situation shift.

auch noch
accomm. no accomm. accomm. no accomm.
Eckardt 2007 ✓(?) ✓(?)
Umbach 2012
Grubic 2018

Section 4.1 explains how the respective topic situations of the answers are derived in the accommodation and non-accommodation cases. Sections 4.2–4.3 discuss necessary amendments to Grubic’s (2018) account.

4.1 The topic situation

The topic situation for a sentence is derived via its QUD. In a QUD hierarchy, the topmost question (What is the way things are?, see Roberts 2012) is about our actual world, w0, and each subquestion narrows down the part of this world talked about (Schwarz 2009). For example, in (55), the subquestions are about a proper part of the topic situation of the superquestion.1920

    1. (55)

According to Kratzer (2020), a topic situation is an actual situation—i.e., a part of our world w0—which exemplifies the question extension. The question extension is a proposition, the set of situations in which the exhaustive true answer to the question is true. For example, if Bertha walked the first 11 stages of the way of St. James 5 years ago is the exhaustive true answer to the first question in (55), the question extension is the set of situations in which Berta walked the first 11 stages of the way of St. James 5 years ago.

Exemplification can be defined as in (56) (a variant of the definition in Kratzer (2020).

(56) Exemplification: A situation s exemplifies a proposition p if p is true in s and
  a. either p is true in all subsituations of s,
  b. or there is no subsituation of s in which p is true.

Both disjuncts (a) and (b) take care that the situation contains nothing irrelevant for the truth of the proposition. Which disjunct is needed depends on properties of the proposition, e.g., telicity. Consider (57a), with a telic predicate. If a situation s contains everything that is needed in order to make (57a) true and nothing irrelevant, then there is no subsituation of s for which (57a) is true—because the airplane wouldn’t be finished in that subsituation. In contrast, (57b) is atelic: if Josephine flew an airplane in a situation s (and no other thing irrelevant to Josephine flying an airplane happened), she also flew an airplane in all subsituations of s.

(57) a. Josephine built an airplane.
  b. Josephine flew an airplane.

Consider now the two cases relevant for our experiment. Let’s assume that the answers provided in the example are true in their respective topic situation. First, consider the non-accommodation case (found with noch and under one reading of auch). Here, the topic situation derived via the first QUD in (55) is the actual situation, five years ago, in which Bertha walked the first 11 stages (and nothing else happened), and the topic situation derived via the second QUD is the actual situation, last year, in which Bertha walked the remaining 21 stages (and nothing else happened). The respective answers are thus exhaustive true answers to their QUDs. Next, consider the accommodation case, where it is accommodated that Bertha also walked the first 11 stages last year. Here again, the topic situation of the first answer is the actual situation, five years ago, in which Bertha walked the first 11 stages (and nothing else happened). Since the exhaustive true answer to the second question is 32 stages, the topic situation provided by the second QUD is the actual situation, last year, in which Bertha walked all 32 stages (and nothing else happened). Both the accommodated answer (11 stages) and the overt answer (21 stages) to the second QUD are thus non-exhaustive, partial answers, but together entail the exhaustive answer.

4.2 Amendment 1: Reassessing auch

We propose an amendment to the previous QUD accounts for auch. In these accounts, auch was assumed to indicate that the QUD is re-opened with respect to a new domain, e.g., (58): the speaker first assumes that the addressee wants to know who of A and B ran, and then remembers that C and D are also relevant, and re-opens the QUD to address them. Each answer is thus exhaustive.

    1. (58)
    1. (59)

This assumption can however not be upheld here in this form, because the two answers would involve different topic situations (Who of A and B ran? is exemplified by the actual situation in which A is running, and Who of C and D ran? by the actual situation in which D is running). This would be problematic for our proposal: if auch required an extended domain, and an extended domain always entailed a topic situation shift, then noch should always be felicitous when auch is. In order to solve this problem and derive a common topic situation for both questions, the complete domain {A,B,C,D} is necessary, see (59).

Besides this theory-internal reason, here is an additional, independent empirical motivation stemming from our own data to reject the idea that auch obligatorily involves a change of domain. Note that examples without a topic situation shift are degraded with complement anaphors (60), just like simple examples with overt, unchanged domains (61). The parallel behavior of (60) and (61) suggests that our experimental items, which all contained complement anaphora as in (62), may all implicitly involve an overt, unchanged domain (here: the stages), just like in the more explicit example (60).

(60) Q: How much of the Way of St. James did Bertha walk last year?
  A: ?She walked the first 11 stages, and she also walked the remaining 21 stages.
(61) Who out of A, B, C and D ran? – ?A ran, and D ran, too.

If this is correct, then there is no shift in domain, either, in the auch reading with accommodation, as shown in (63): the second and third QUD are identical, they involve the same domain and the same topic situation. Nevertheless, auch is perfectly felicitous here. Thus, the explanation for the degradedness of (60)–(61) cannot be that auch necessarily requires a domain extension.

(62) Five years ago, Bertha walked the first eleven stages of the Way of St. James.
  Last year, she also walked the last 21 stages of the Way of St. James.
    1. (63)

We suggest that domain extension with auch is not obligatory, but arises in some cases due to the Gricean maxim of manner: there is a shorter way to answer in (60) and (61), so a long answer should be avoided. If the maxim of manner is ostensibly violated, the implicature arises that this was done for a reason, e.g., to extend the domain because the speaker remembered some relevant further alternatives.21 In the accommodation example (62), there is no violation of the maxim of manner because the answer provided is as short as the alternative full answer (Last year, she walked all 32 stages). Thus an extension of the domain of alternatives is not always obligatory with auch.

For unstressed auch, we thus suggest to depart from the earlier proposals in §2 and merely state that auch introduces a presupposition that an alternative answer to the QUD (about the same or a different topic situation) is contextually provided.

4.3 Amendment 2: Reassessing noch

In this section, we want to propose a QUD account which takes the following properties of additive noch into account (64): First, with respect to its antecedent, the noch-sentence involves a different focused constituent AND a different topic situation. Second, we have to take into account Eckardt’s (2007) observations that the domain of alternatives seems more coherent than in the case of auch and that there is a subsequent negative phase.

    1. (64)
    1. Um
    2. at
    1. 3
    2. 3
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. Otto
    2. Otto
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. SCHNAPS
    2. schnaps
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. ‘At 3am, Otto also had a schnaps.’
      1. Antecedent of the form ‘At t, Otto had a X’
      2. Domain of alternatives coherent in some sense
      3. Subsequent negative phase: Otto had nothing else after that

Our main assumption is that there is a question distinct from the current QUD (imaginable as its superquestion), for which the two answers related via noch contextually entail an answer (see Gast & van der Auwera 2011 for additive-scalar particles). In the case of additive noch, we assume a superquestion asking for the extent of some development (e.g., How much of the Way of St. James did Bertha walk?) and two subquestions posing this question about two different subsituations. The noch sentence contextually entails a stronger answer to this superquestion than the preceding/presupposed answer(s), namely that she walked 32 stages, see (66). Relatedly, the topic situation of the preceding answer is a proper part of that of the contextually entailed stronger answer, see (67).22

    1. (65)
(66) (67)

This QUD hierarchy accounts for the fact that the two overt answers involve different topic situations as well as different foci, cf. (64a). The superquestion asking for the extent of a development is responsible for the inference that the focus alternatives are coherent, cf. (64b). If further alternatives were under discussion, this would lead to an implicature that those alternatives are false (Eckardt’s subsequent negative phase), cf. (64c).

We assume that the subsequent negative phase, as already briefly discussed above in §2.2.1, is due to an exhaustivity implicature (via the Gricean maxim of quantity): a (defeasible) inference that the current answer together with its antecedent entail the strongest true answer to the QUD, and that thus all stronger alternatives are false. We believe that it is not hard-wired into the meaning of noch, and will ignore it here.23

The coherence of focus alternatives (leading to Eckardt’s suggestion of a “fixed and stable domain”), however, requires further discussion. For example, in (68), the mentioned alternatives are part of a salient set of texts that belong together by virtue of being part of the same newspaper. In contrast, (69) contains two unrelated alternatives (short story and comic book), and noch requires further context or accommodation in order to be felicitous here, e.g., that they are both part of Anna’s to-read list or part of an assignment to read as much as possible.24

    1. (68)
    1. (Yesterday, Anna read the business part of the newspaper.)
    1. Heute
    2. today
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. sie
    2. she
    1. (noch)
    2. still
    1. den
    2. the
    1. Politikteil
    2. politics.section
    1. gelesen.
    2. read
    1. ‘Today, she additionally read the politics section.’
    1. (69)
    1. (Yesterday, Anna read a short story.)
    1. Heute
    2. today
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. sie
    2. she
    1. (?noch)
    2. still
    1. ihr
    2. her
    1. neues
    2. new
    1. Comicheft
    2. comic.book
    1. gelesen.
    2. read
    1. ‘Today, she additionally read her new comic book.’

We think that this is related to the intuition that noch seems to indicate a continuation of a development: the assertion contextually entails that some previous (presupposed) development is continued by the asserted event; e.g., that reading the politics section advances the progress of reading the complete newspaper in (68). We assume that the superquestion is responsible for this sense of development: in the relevant examples, noch involves a how much/many superquestion,25 i.e. noch restricts the kind of superquestions available (see Coppock & Beaver 2013 for an account of exclusives as restricting their QUDs), and the answers ranked on a scale such as (66) are related to a salient independent measure. The latter idea is adapted from a proposal by Greenberg (2010) for additive more. In (69), the independent measure might e.g. be how happy Anna’s teacher will be, which we represent as a further degree QUD called Qdev in (70)–(71).26

(70) The stronger the answer to QUDsup, the stronger the answer to QUDdev.
(71) ∃f∀p,p′ ∈ Qsup ∀q,q′ ∈ Qdev[f(p) = q & f(p′) = q′ → [p′ ≤ p → q′ ≤ q]]

Thus, in addition to a mapping between alternatives and situations (66)–(67), there is also a mapping between alternatives and an independent measure.

To sum up, we propose that noch (Scurr) indicates a QUD strategy such as (72), with the following restrictions.

(72)
 
  1. Qprev and Qcurr differ with respect to their topic situation;

  2. the (other) backgrounded material in Qprev and Qcurr is identical;

  3. Qsup asks about the extent of some development;

  4. Aprev and Acurr both contextually entail an answer to Qsup;

The restriction in (ii) is shared by auch, and arguably also (iv).

5 Outlook

5.1 Extending the account to further examples

In this section, we first return to examples where the topic shift is less clear, e.g. (73).27 Then we discuss whether the nature of the predicate (e.g. its Aktionsart) has any effect on the interpretation with noch.

    1. (73)
    1. (Otto had a beer.)
    1. Ansonsten
    2. otherwise
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. SCHNAPS
    2. schnaps
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. ‘In addition, he drank a schnaps.’

This example lacks an overt temporal topic situation shifter such as a temporal adverbial. However, we argue that noch can also be licensed by overt domain extension indicators such as sonst/ansonsten (= ‘else, otherwise’), etc., see e.g. (74) with an overt domain (alcoholic beverages), suggesting that the noch-sentence adds an alternative (mineral water) outside this overt domain.

    1. (74)
    1. (What alcoholic beverages did Otto drink? — Otto had a beer…)
    1. Ansonsten
    2. Otherwise
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. (nur)
    2. only
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. ein
    2. a
    1. Mineralwasser
    2. mineral-water
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. ‘Apart from that, he only had a mineral water in addition.’

The reason why re-opening a QUD with respect to a new (extended) domain also gives rise to a topic situation shift is that the topic situation is derived via the question extension (according to Kratzer 2020). Thus, when the domain changes, the question extension differs, too. It is predicted that noch is licensed whenever the domain is overtly extended, if the other conditions for a felicitous use of noch are satisfied (see §4.3).28

We now briefly discuss Aktionsart. A reviewer pointed out that (75) easily receives a reading under which Bardo has a cello and a violin this year.

    1. (75)
    1. (Last year, Bardo had a violin.)
    1. Dieses
    2. this
    1. Jahr
    2. year
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. ein
    2. a
    1. Cello.
    2. cello.
    1. ‘This year, he has a cello in addition.’

Assuming the account of topic situations discussed in §4.1, this is not problematic: a situation exemplifies a proposition with an atelic predicate if it does not contain any subsituation in which the proposition is false, e.g., in (75), a situation containing everything needed for the truth of Bardo has a violin, but nothing else. As Kratzer (2020) discusses, the maximal (spatio-temporally connected) situation of Bardo having a cello can exceed the topic situation and can e.g. continue this year. Therefore, it can hold for this year that Bardo has both instruments without assuming that anything is accommodated.

Examples with temporal adverbials are thus not suitable to show that the readings found in our experiment (with telic predicates) are also available for sentences with stative predicates. If we use a locative instead, these readings become available. In (76), our intuition is that the variant with noch can only receive a reading where there is a single plant in Bardo’s living room. The variant with auch additionally allows for a reading where Bardo has a palm tree and a cactus in his living room.

    1. (76)
    1. (In his bedroom, Bardo has a palm tree.)
    1. In
    2. in
    1. seinem
    2. his
    1. Wohnzimmer
    2. living-room
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. auch/noch
    2. also/still
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. Kaktus.
    2. cactus
    1. ‘In his living room, he (also) has a cactus.’

To sum up this section, we depart from Grubic’s (2018) account in suggesting that a domain extension also leads to a topic situation shift. As far as we can tell, additive noch is compatible with different Aktionsarten, as long as the conditions described in §4.3 are met.

5.2 Open questions

Open questions remain concerning the data that Grubic’s (2018) account is based on. The data were the behavior of additive particles (i) in questions, (ii) with dann, (iii) accented NOCH, and (iv) the co-occurrence of auch and noch.

Concerning questions, the proposal was that since with auch, the QUD is reopened about the same topic situation, it is used to signal that a previous answer is considered incomplete. Theiler (2019: p. 347) notes that this wrongly predicts such questions to be felicitous if the questioner knows that there is another true answer, but does not know which, as in (77).

    1. (77)
    1. (Over the summer, every student has to read two books of their choice. Back at school, A is reporting what she read.)
    1.  
    1. A:
    1. On vacation, I read Emma.
    1.  
    1. B:
    1. Okay,
    2. okay
    1. cool.
    2. cool
    1. #Und
    2.   and
    1. was
    2. what
    1. hast
    2. have
    1. du
    2. you
    1. auch
    2. also
    1. gelesen?
    2. read
    1. ‘Okay, cool. #And what did you also read?’

Theiler also mentions a further kind of wh-question (called summoning question) in which auch is felicitous. This kind of question “is posed directly to a group of people, with the aim of finding out who of these people have a certain property” (Theiler 2019: p. 348).

As noted in Eckardt (2007: p. 86), these examples involve an (overt or covert) change of domain (e.g., who at this table in Eckardt’s example (78)).

    1. (78)
    1. (Waitress first takes orders for coffee at table nr. 1. Turning then to table nr. 2, she asks:)
    1. Wer
    2. who
    1. an
    2. at
    1. diesem
    2. this
    1. Tisch
    2. table
    1. will
    2. wants
    1. auch
    2. also
    1. /
    2.  
    1. #noch
    2. still
    1. Kaffee?
    2. coffee
    1. ‘Who at this table wants coffee, too?’

While this may explain the felicity of auch, the current account wrongly predicts noch to be felicitous, too. Perhaps the lack of coherence can explain the infelicity, but further research would be needed to test this, and to address the criticism concerning (77).

The second kind of example concerned the behavior of noch and auch with dann, which can either mean ‘then’ (danntemp) or ‘in addition’ (danndisc). Grubic (2018) suggested that dann is a topic-situation shifter under both readings, since noch is infelicitous in simple examples without danntemp/disc (or similar, e.g., sonst/ansonsten ‘otherwise’). As noted in §5.1 above, we think that sonst/ansonsten indicate domain extension, indirectly leading to a topic situation shift. We believe that this analysis can be extended to danndisc. Support for this view comes from the behavior of dann with complement anaphora such as andere (‘other’) (79). As argued in §4.2, complement anaphora make the complete domain of alternatives (here: the two beers) explicit. In such examples, according to our intuitions, danntemp patterns like a temporal adverbial (79a) while danndisc patterns like domain-extenders (79b).29 The latter are odd because the other beer is already part of the domain.

    1. (79)
    1. (Peter drank one of the two beers.)
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. Danntemp
    2. then
    1. /
    2. /
    1. Später
    2. later
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. noch/auch
    2. still/also
    1. das
    2. the
    1. andere
    2. other
    1. Bier
    2. beer
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. ‘Then/later, he also drank the other beer.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ??/#Danndisc/??Sonst
    2. in.addition
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. noch/auch
    2. still/also
    1. das
    2. the
    1. andere
    2. other
    1. Bier
    2. beer
    1. getrunken.
    2. drunk
    1. ‘He drank the other beer in addition.’

Examples containing danndisc in which domain extension is possible can then be analyzed in parallel to examples with ansonsten/sonst — insertion of noch is licensed, because a change in the domain entails a change of the topic situation (see §4.2).

The third kind of example is accented NOCH. Grubic (2018) adopted the assumption made in Umbach (2012) that the indefinite expression following noch is in focus, and that the alternatives are other individuals of the same kind.

However, neither account addresses the question why this is only possible with (singular) indefinites or numerals, e.g., noch ein Buch (lit. ‘still a/one book’), noch zwei Bücher (lit. ‘still two books’), but not *noch Bücher (lit. ‘still books’). Perhaps the reason lies in the syntactic position and corresponding semantic type of NOCH, which seems to differ from that of the unaccented noch (80).

    1. (80)
    1. (Otto spoke to a student.)
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. Dann
    2. then
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. noch
    2. still
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Lehrerin
    2. teacher
    1. gesprochen.
    2. spoke
    1. ‘In addition, he talked to a teacher.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Dann
    2. then
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. er
    2. he
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. NOCH
    2. still
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Schülerin
    2. student
    1. gesprochen
    2. spoke
    1. ‘Then he talked to another student.’

Greenberg (2010) proposes for additive more (in, e.g., then he met one more student) that it first combines with an argument of type d—a numeral (3) or measure phrase (3 litres). Since German ein is ambiguous between a numeral and an indefinite article, it may be that NOCH is restricted to numerals and measure phrases, too. Stressed NOCH and its relation to nochmal (= repetitive ‘again’) is another topic left for further work—what it shares with unaccented additive noch is that it appears to require a topic situation shift, as well as a continuation of a development.30

Our reassessment of auch and noch leads to a prediction—differing from Grubic (2018), see the discussion of ex. (38) above—concerning the combination auch noch. The prediction is that this combination should be possible in exactly those cases where noch alone is possible, because auch has a weaker contribution than noch: it merely requires an alternative answer to the QUD. As pointed out in fn.16 above, a reviewer proposed that auch noch behaves like auch instead. Thus, further work is needed to investigate the behavior of auch noch.

A final open question is the relation of additive noch to other uses of noch. Since such a unified account is outside the scope of this paper, we will only provide some comments. We believe that a unified analysis needs to incorporate the following properties of noch: Noch always involves a higher superquestion asking for the extent of a development—with temporal noch, it is an until when-question, while its subquestions are polar question about different times (81). The answer containing noch always contextually entails a stronger answer to the superquestion than the presupposed other answer (in terms of entailment — (82)), which is assumed—via the Gricean maxim of quantity—to be the strongest answer to the superquestion, leading to the implicature that stronger answers are false.

    1. (81)
    1. (82)

Under this proposal, in the case of both additive and temporal noch, some aspect of the topic situation is shifted, whereby temporal noch is restricted to a temporal shift (but recall that there is a closely related variant where the shift is locative, cf. (9)).

The superquestion is also responsible for the coherence between the two separate answers. For temporal noch in (81), only further, later instantiations of the same sleeping event count as a continuation of a development in terms of the super-QUD.

6 Summary

We presented an experiment testing the behavior of additive noch (‘still’, ‘in addition’) and auch (‘also/too’) in examples like (83) in order to investigate the hypothesis that a shift in topic situations plays a role for the meaning of noch but not for auch (following Grubic 2018). Our main question was whether the respective additive particle would lead to, e.g., the accommodation of ‘Last year, she walked the first eleven stages’.

    1. (83)
    1. (Five years ago, Bertha walked the first eleven stages of the Way of St. James.)
    1. Letztes
    2. last
    1. Jahr
    2. year
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. sie
    2. she
    1. auch/noch
    2. also/still
    1. die
    2. the
    1. letzten
    2. last
    1. 21
    2. 21
    1. Etappen
    2. stages
    1. gelaufen.
    2. walked
    1. ‘Last year, she also/additionally walked the last 21 stages.’

We tested three different kinds of examples: ones in which accommodation was predicted to be pragmatically preferred, ones in which accommodation was predicted to be dispreferred, and ones which were neutral in this respect—the latter were used as the baseline.

Grubic’s (2018) account predicts that noch does not lead to accommodation, whereas auch typically but not necessarily does. For the baseline context, we thus predicted that ratings would be high for both particles, but that they would be interpreted differently: accommodation would take place with auch but not with noch. In the context where accommodation is pragmatically preferred (+REP), we predicted that noch would be judged worse than auch. In the context where accommodation is dispreferred (–REP), we predicted both particles to be felicitous, but we predicted that auch would not lead to accommodation (in contrast to the baseline examples). Both predictions were borne out.

Data accessibility statement

The auditory materials, the collected data, and the scripts used for statistical analysis are available on OSF (Open Science Foundation). DOI: https://doi.org/10.17605/OSF.IO/R97KC.

Additional files

The additional files for this article can be found as follows:

Appendix A

Items used in the plausibility pre-test. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.1275.s1

Appendix B

Items used in the main experiment. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.1275.s2

Appendix C

Fillers used in the main experiment. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.1275.s3

Notes

  1. Stressed AUCH, in contrast, is argued to be topic-sensitive (Krifka 1998). [^]
  2. There is also a stressed variant of NOCH—see (20) below—but it is arguably not topic-sensitive. [^]
  3. Extended, in Umbach’s terminology, means that the immediate QUD of the noch answer involves a entirely distinct domain of alternatives than the antecedent QUD, rather than a larger (superset) domain. [^]
  4. Umbach also provides a proposal for stressed AUCH, which will not be relevant for the current proposal. [^]
  5. This is seen as a repair mechanism in the sense that Roberts (2012: p. 45) discusses for implicature cancellation in general: “[…] ‘implicature cancellation’ might more aptly be called ‘post hoc clarification (by the speaker) and revision (by the hearer) of intended context’”. [^]
  6. In (34), no domain is shown because, as will become clearer below, Grubic’s (2018) account does not make any predictions with respect to the domain. [^]
  7. We now believe that there is more to these examples than assumed in Grubic (2018), see §6. [^]
  8. Both Eckardt and Umbach briefly discuss such examples, too (Eckardt 2007: p. 93, Umbach 2012 p. 1856f). Eckardt proposes that the positive phase requirement of noch is retained, but not the fixed domain. Umbach proposes that when they associate with the same constituent “auch [marks] a supplement to the previous answer while noch indicates an extension of the domain of the [QUD].” [^]
  9. A reviewer asks why precisely this proposition is accommodated. Speakers use all available cues to identify possible information to be accommodated (Grubic & Wierzba 2019)—arguably, in this case, an immediately preceding parallel answer, if plausible, can provide this identifying information. [^]
  10. The study was prepared and run with the help of Annika Stark in the context of Stark’s Bachelor’s thesis (Stark 2017). We present an extended analysis of the results here. In the same context, another small-scale experiment was run (comparing auch, noch, and the combination auch noch), which we do not report here. [^]
  11. For our predictions, it is not crucial to distinguish between implausible/impossible continuations. However, we had the impression that this option made the task more natural. [^]
  12. The examples are in English for readability; all German items can be found in Appendix A. [^]
  13. Percentages do not always total to 100 due to rounding. [^]
  14. The model was fit following the recommendations for identifying parsimonious models by Bates et al. (2015a), using the R packages lme4 and lmerTest (R Core Team 2016, Bates et al. 2015b, Kuznetsova et al. 2017). [^]
  15. In this point, we deviate from the pre-registration: there, we set 80% as the exclusion criterion; after pre-registering, but before data analysis, we decided to use only these four items as controls and therefore set the criterion to 75%. [^]
  16. An anonymous reviewer suggests that the combination auch noch is completely felicitous in +REP contexts (pace Grubic 2018) and that the participants in this subgroup might be adding a silent auch to the sentence. In order to evaluate this proposal, the behaviour of auch noch requires further study — cf. §5.2. [^]
  17. See Tiemann (2014) for results suggesting that participants ignore presuppositions when they are not in the position to challenge the speaker. [^]
  18. In principle, another possibility to explore this question would be to check for a correlation with the behavior in other cases of presupposition failure. Our fillers did include cases of presupposition failure with nochmal/wieder ‘again’ (cf. Appendix C), but since we only collected two data points per participant and condition for these fillers, we refrain from exploring this potential correlation here based on our data. [^]
  19. Note that situations need not be spatio-temporally connected (Kratzer 2020), i.e. there can be a situation consisting of a space-time chunk five years ago and another one year ago, without the years inbetween. [^]
  20. According to Hohaus (2015), sentence-initial framesetters like five years ago add a presuppositional restriction to the topic situation (i).
    (i) [[FRAME]] = λps,t.λqs,t.λss:p(s). q(s)(simplified)
    [^]
  21. A reviewer provides (i) showing that there can also be other reasons for a longer answer: in contrast to (i-a), (i-b) is fine, because it involves additional information about the last two bottles.
      1. (i)
      1. (During the summer holidays, Quentin drank five wine bottles from his supply.)
      1.  
      1. a.
      1. ??Er
      2. he
      1. hat
      2. has
      1. auch
      2. also
      1. die
      2. the
      1. letzten
      2. last
      1. zwei
      2. two
      1. Flaschen
      2. bottles
      1. ausgetrunken.
      2. drunk.up
      1. ‘He also finished the last two wine bottles.’
      1.  
      1. b.
      1. Er
      2. he
      1. hat
      2. has
      1. auch
      2. also
      1. die
      2. the
      1. letzten
      2. last
      1. zwei
      2. two
      1. Flaschen
      2. bottles
      1. ausgetrunken,
      2. drunk.up
      1. aber
      2. but
      1. mit
      2. with
      1. der
      2. the
      1. Hilfe
      2. help
      1. von
      2. of
      1. Otto.
      2. Otto
      1. ‘He also finished the last two bottles, but with the help of Otto.’
    [^]
  22. Thus, under our account, noch is a scalar/scale-alignment particle, cf. Krifka (2000). [^]
  23. In fact, example (13) above where noch is used repeatedly, shows that not all additional answers are required to be negative; and our experimental items, where all answers are positive (due to remaining, other, etc.) show that noch does not require that there are additional negative answers. [^]
  24. The latter case goes against Eckardt’s intuition that there is a finite set of alternatives. [^]
  25. The reason behind Eckardt’s intuition of a fixed domain may be that the question is often partitive (e.g. how many of the items on the to-read list did Anna read?). [^]
  26. Noch can also felicitously occur in contexts in which the development is not intentional or planned:
      1. (i)
      1. (The roof of the old house is falling apart. Yesterday, some roof tiles fell off.)
      1. Heute
      2. today
      1. ist
      2. is
      1. noch
      2. still
      1. der
      2. the
      1. Schornstein
      2. chimney
      1. eingestürzt.
      2. collapsed
      1. ‘Today, the chimney collapsed in addition.’
    [^]
  27. We tentatively assume a similar analysis for examples with discourse dann, as discussed in §5.2. [^]
  28. In our examples with ansonsten ‘otherwise’, the development requirement does not seem to hold in the same way as in sentences with a situation shift via temporal expressions. The same holds for (i), which an anonymous reviewer provided.
      1. (i)
      1. (Where can I get a good coffee around here?)
      1. Bei
      2. at
      1. Café
      2. Café
      1. Lotti
      2. Lotti
      1. und
      2. and
      1. außerdem
      2. moreover
      1. noch
      2. still
      1. bei
      2. at
      1. Schwarzer
      2. Schwarzer
      1. Kater.
      2. Kater
      1. ‘At Cafe Lotti and, apart from that, at Schwarzer Kater.’
    We tentatively suggest that in such cases, the relevant independent measure (QUDdev) might be discourse-oriented and have to do with giving as many helpful answers as possible. [^]
  29. Concerning (79b), we agree with Umbach that auch is infelicitous with danndisc (though felicitous with sonst/außerdem) — further research is needed to find out why. [^]
  30. Stressed noch is also found in comparatives (i). If this is also a case of additive noch, as Umbach (2009) proposes, then this constitutes an example that is not explained by our proposal.
      1. (i)
      1. Adam ist größer als Peter. ‘Adam is taller than Peter.’
      1. Bertha
      2. Bertha
      1. ist
      2. is
      1. NOCH
      2. still
      1. größer
      2. taller
      1. als
      2. than
      1. Adam.
      2. Adam
      1. ‘Bertha is even taller than Adam.’
    [^]

Acknowledgements

The authors wish to thank the anonymous reviewers as well as Mareike Philipp, Joseph P. De Veaugh-Geiss and the audiences at the FATEP workshop (Focus Alternatives: Theoretical and Empirical Perspectives) at the Humboldt university in Berlin and the syntax/semantics colloquium at the university of Potsdam for their helpful comments.

Funding information

The publication of this paper was funded by the Open Access Publication Fund of the University of Potsdam, supported by Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (German Research Foundation) within the framework of the Open Access Publishing program. We would like to thank the DFG and the University of Potsdam for this support.

Competing interests

The authors have no competing interests to declare.

Author contributions

Mira Grubic wrote the first draft of the introduction, literature overview, discussion and outlook/summary. Marta Wierzba pre-registered the experiments, performed the statistical analyses, wrote the first draft of the sections on the experiments and made our data available (see ‘Data availability’ above). We designed and ran the experiments together, and both contributed to all sections in subsequent versions of the paper.

References

Austin, John L. 1950. Truth. In Geoffrey J. Warnock & James O. Urmson (eds.), Philosophical Papers, 117–133. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/019283021X.003.0005

Barwise, Jon & John Etchemendy. 1987. The liar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Bates, Douglas, Martin Mächler, Ben Bolker & Steve Walker. 2015b. Fitting linear mixed-effects models using lme4. Journal of Statistical Software 1(67). 1–48. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.18637/jss.v067.i01

Bates, Douglas, Reinhold Kliegl, Shravan Vasishth & Harald Baayen. 2015a. Parsimonious mixed models. arXiv.org e-print archive. arXiv:1506.04967 [stat.ME].

Beaver, David & Brady Clark. 2008. Sense and sensitivity: How focus determines meaning. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

Beck, Sigrid. 2016. Discourse related readings of scalar particles. In Mary Moroney, Carol-Rose Little, Jacob Collard & Dan Burgdorf (eds.), Proceedings of SALT 26. 142–165. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v26i0.3783

Beck, Sigrid. 2020. Readings of scalar particles: noch/still. Linguistics and Philosophy 43. 1–67. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-018-09256-1

Coppock, Elizabeth & David I. Beaver. 2013. Principles of the exclusive muddle. Journal of Semantics 31(3). 371–432. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/fft007

Eckardt, Regine. 2007. ‘Was noch?’ Navigating in question answer discourse. In Andreas Späth (ed.), Interfaces and interface conditions, 78–95. Berlin: De Gruyter.

Frazier, Lyn & Charles Clifton. 2018. Topic situations: Coherence by inclusion. Journal of Memory and Language 103. 176–190. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/j.jml.2018.08.006

Gast, Volker & Johan van der Auwera. 2011. Scalar additive operators in the languages of Europe. Language 87(1). 1–53. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2011.0008

Greenberg, Yael. 2010. Additivity in the domain of eventualities (or: Oliver Twist’s more). In Martin Prinzhorn, Viola Schmitt & Sarah Zobel (eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 14. 151–167.

Grubic, Mira. 2018. Two strategies of reopening QUDs – evidence from German auch & noch. In Robert Truswell, Chris Cummins, Caroline Heycock, Brian Rabern & Hannah Rohde (eds.), Proceedings of SuB 21. 517–534.

Grubic, Mira & Marta Wierzba. 2019. Presupposition accommodation of the German additive particle auch (= “too”). Frontiers in Communication 4. 15. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3389/fcomm.2019.00015

Hohaus, Vera. 2015. Context and composition: How presuppositions restrict the interpretation of free variables. Tübingen: TOBIAS-lib Publikationssystem.

Ippolito, Michela. 2007. On the meaning of some focus-sensitive particles. Natural Language Semantics 15. 1–34. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-007-9004-0

Jasinskaja, Katja & Henk Zeevat. 2009. Explaining conjunction systems: Russian, English, German. In Arndt Riester & Torgrim Solstad (eds.), Proceedings of SuB 13. 231–245.

Kim, Christina S. 2012. Generating alternatives: Interpreting focus in discourse. University of Rochester dissertation.

Kim, Christina S. 2015. Presupposition satisfaction, locality and discourse constituency. In Florian Schwarz (ed.), Experimental perspectives on presuppositions, 109–134. Cham: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-07980-6_5

Klein, Wolfgang. 2007. About the German particles schon and noch. Ms., Max Planck Institute for Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen.

Klein, Wolfgang. 2008. The topic situation. In Bernt Ahrenholz, Ursula Bredel, Wolfgang Klein, Martina Rost-Roth & Romuald Skiba (eds.), Empirische Forschung und Theoriebildung, 287–305. Frankfurt am Main: Lang.

Kratzer, Angelika. 2020. Situations in natural language semantics. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University fall 2020 edn.

Krifka, Manfred. 1998. Additive particles under stress. In Proceedings of SALT 8. 111–128. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v8i0.2799

Krifka, Manfred. 2000. Alternatives for aspectual particles: Semantics of still and already. In Lisa J. Conathan, Jeff Good, Darya Kavitskaya, Alyssa B. Wulf & Alan C. L. Yu (eds.), Proceedings of the twenty-sixth annual meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, 401–412. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/bls.v26i1.1125

Kripke, Saul A. 2009. Presupposition and anaphora: Remarks on the formulation of the projection problem. Linguistic Inquiry 40(3). 367–386. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2009.40.3.367

Kuznetsova, Alexandra, Per B. Brockhoff & Rune H. B. Christensen. 2017. lmertest package: Tests in linear mixed effects models. Journal of Statistical Software 13(82). 1–26. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.18637/jss.v082.i13

Lewis, David. 1986. On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

Löbner, Sebastian. 1989. German schonerstnoch: An integrated analysis. Linguistics and Philosophy 12. 167–212. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00627659

Maienborn, Claudia. 2001. On the position and interpretation of locative modifiers. Natural Language Semantics 9. 191–240. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1012405607146

R Core Team. 2016. R: A language and environment for statistical computing. https://www.R-project.org.

Roberts, Craige. 2012. Information structure: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. Semantics and Pragmatics 5(6). 1–69. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/sp.5.6

Schwarz, Florian. 2009. Two types of definites in natural language. University of Massachusetts dissertation.

Stark, Annika. 2017. Die additiven Partikel auch und noch im Deutschen. B.Sc. thesis, University of Potsdam.

Starschenko, Alexej & Marta Wierzba. 2020. L-Rex: Linguistic rating experiments [software]. https://github.com/2e2a/l-rex/.

Theiler, Nadine. 2019. When additive particles can associate with wh-phrases. In M. Teresa Espinal, Elena Castroviejo, Manuel Leonetti, Louise McNally & Cristina Real-Puigdollers (eds.), Proceedings of SuB 23. 347–364.

Tiemann, Sonja. 2014. The processing of wieder (‘again’) and other presupposition triggers. Eberhard Karls Universität Tübingen dissertation.

Umbach, Carla. 2009. Comparatives combined with additive particles: The case of German noch. In Proceedings of SuB 13. 543–558.

Umbach, Carla. 2012. Strategies of additivity: German additive noch compared to auch. Lingua 122(15). 1843–1863. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2012.01.011

von Stechow, Arnim. 1990. Focusing and backgrounding operators. In Werner Abraham (ed.), Discourse particles, 37–84. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/pbns.12.04ste