1 Introduction

This paper is concerned with mit ‘with’ as a free particle in German. In this use, mit forms an independent syntactic constituent that contrasts with typical prepositions by lacking an explicit internal argument; see (1) for exemplification.1

    1. (1)
    1. a.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. fährt
    2. rides
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. nach
    2. to
    1. Rom.
    2. Rome
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people riding to Rome.’

The previous work agrees that mit in these cases relates to the verbally introduced eventuality; see Zifonun (1996/1997; 1999); Zifonun et al. (1997); Bücker (2012). However, the particular analyses of this adverbial free mit (= mitadv) differ considerably. According to Zifonun (1996/1997; 1999), mitadv consists of a preposition and a retrievable internal argument. This ellipsis approach assigns (1a) the interpretation in (2).2

(2) Ben is tinkering with a soapbox with someone else.

By contrast, Bücker (2012) considers mitadv an additive particle such as auch ‘also’. This additive approach assigns (1a) the bipartite interpretation in (3).

(3) a. assertion: Ben is tinkering with a soapbox.
  b. presupposition: Someone different from Ben is tinkering with a soapbox.

The first aim of this paper is to disprove both analyses by a close inspection of the semantics and pragmatics of mitadv. For instance, mitadv is not focus-sensitive in the way auch is, which is why it cannot adjoin the alleged focal expression in the prefield; see the contrast in (4).

    1. (4)
    1. {Auch
    2. {also
    1. /
    2. /
    1. *Mit}
    2. mitadv}
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox

Furthermore, the additive analysis does not capture that mitadv introduces an accompaniment by participation in an eventuality. One indication is that (1a) suggests that Ben and the implicit alternative are tinkering with the same soapbox; the additive analysis in (3) does not provide an anchor for such a conclusion. The ellipsis account is sensitive to an accompaniment, but in the wrong way: according to (2), the retrievable PP-internal participant is a comitative. This supports various interpretations; for instance, the relevant participant could be a co-agent of the tinkering, but he could also relate to it without tinkering himself. This does not comply with intuitions regarding the example in (1a). For one, (1a) identifies the explicit subject as the participant that is accompanying an eventuality; furthermore, the interpretation is restricted to some form of co-agency. I will therefore argue that (1a) receives an interpretation as paraphrased in (5).

(5) Ben is accompanying an implicit tinkering with a soapbox by himself tinkering with the soapbox.

According to this alternative proposal, mitadv modifies the verbal eventuality description in such a way that the explicit subject is said to accompany an implicit eventuality by participating in a corresponding eventuality. In contrast to the previous work, I will also sketch a formal treatment of mitadv.

In addition to examples such as (1), free mit licenses an intriguing second use, namely, it can also be combined with the superlative, as in (6) (= mitsup). As predicted by the distribution of the superlative in general, mitsup can contribute to predicatives, as in (6a), to adverbials, as in (6b), or to objects, as in (6c); see also Zifonun et al. (1997: 2147–2148).

    1. (6)
    1. a.
    1. In
    2. in
    1. diesem
    2. this
    1. Raum
    2. room
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. mit
    2. mitsup
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest
    1. ‘Ben belongs to the tallest people in this room.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. In
    2. in
    1. dieser
    2. this
    1. Gruppe
    2. group
    1. kocht
    2. cooks
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. mit
    2. mitsup
    1. am
    2. PTC
    1. besten.
    2. best
    1. ‘Mia cooks in a way that belongs to the best ways of cooking in this group.’
    1.  
    1. c.
    1. In
    2. in
    1. seiner
    2. his
    1. Klasse
    2. class
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. Paul
    2. Paul
    1. mit
    2. mitsup
    1. das
    2. the
    1. eleganteste
    2. most elegant
    1. Outfit.
    2. outfit
    1. ‘Paul has an outfit that belongs to the most elegant outfits in his class.’

Zifonun (1996/1997; 1999) and Bücker (2012) assume that mitsup forms a separate construction. They argue that the uniqueness condition of the superlative is incompatible with their respective analyses of mitadv as an additive or as a retrievable PP. One indication is that the superlative is incompatible with an additive and a PP, as shown in (7). Furthermore, only mitadv can be veridical, as shown by the entailment contrast in (8); see also Bücker (2012: 216).

    1. (7)
    1. #Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. {auch
    2. {also
    1. /
    2. /
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. anderen}
    2. others}
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest
    1.   ‘Ben is {also / together with other people} the tallest.’
    1. (8)
    1. a.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitsup
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest
    1.  
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1.  
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox

The second aim of this paper is to show that the alternative accompaniment-based analysis of mitadv supports a transfer to mitsup and thus their uniform treatment in terms of a generalized free mit (= mitfree). This transfer is based on the independent assumption that the superlative introduces a partition of a context-set according to some context-sensitive cutoff. mitfree then induces the subject argument to accompany an implicit state of complying with this cutoff as borne by at least one implicit alternative individual; in other words, (6a) conveys that Ben belongs to the implicit unique group of tallest people. This compositional approach is attractive because it spares an additional construction; even more importantly, it links the behavior of mitfree to more general questions of distribution and accompaniment that call for principled explanations. For one, the constructional approach does not consider the obvious analogy between the pattern in (8a) and the so-called distributivity problem of plural superlatives in general; see (9) for exemplification and Stateva (2005) and Fitzgibbons et al. (2008) for discussion. The compositional approach will provide a solution that covers both cases; this is certainly more revealing than a treatment of (8a) as a random effect of a separate mitsup construction.

    1. (9)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. und
    2. and
    1. Paul
    2. Paul
    1. sind
    2. are
    1. die
    2. the
    1. größten.
    2. tallest
    1.  
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest

Furthermore, the uniform analysis paves the way for an explanation of puzzling constraints not discussed before. For instance, mitfree is incompatible with the positive and the comparative counterparts of (8a); see (10). Notably, this is completely unexpected under Bücker’s (2012) additive approach to free mit, given that the additive auch would be grammatical here.

    1. (10)
    1. #Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. {groß
    2. {tall
    1. /
    2. /
    1. größer
    2. taller
    1. als
    2. than
    1. Paul}.
    2. Paul}

The crucial independent assumption will be that the positive and the comparative denote particularized properties—so-called tropes—that are inherent to their bearers; see Moltmann (2009; 2013). This inherence renders these predications incompatible with the accompaniment as introduced by mitfree. That is, the variants in (10) are odd because Ben cannot join the height of someone else (irrespective of whether this height is also compared to the height of some further individual). Therefore, mitfree is a revealing test case for the general question of how to capture accompaniment relations within different types of stative expressions; see in addition to Moltmann’s work Bücking (2012); Maienborn (2015); McNally & de Swart (2015); Maienborn & Herdtfelder (2017) for the relevant ontological background.

The present study focuses on a detailed interpretation of mitfree in German from a semantic and pragmatic perspective. Therefore, I will not thoroughly discuss the following aspects. First, I will not dwell on the morpho-syntactic status of mitfree. Based on the results in Zifonun (1996/1997; 1999), I take it for granted that mitfree is not a bound verbal particle, but an independent syntactic constituent. In contrast to verbal particles, mitadv has a neutral base position in front of prepositional objects and adverbial complements and is thus not bound to the final verb position; see (11) and (12). One further indication is that only mitadv can be combined with a particle verb without yielding a new complex particle; see the contrast in (13).3

    1. (11)
    1. a.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. am
    2. with the
    1. Rad
    2. bike
    1. gebastelt.
    2. tinkered
    1. (mitadv)
    2.  
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. am
    2. with the
    1. Rad
    2. bike
    1. mitgebastelt.
    2. with:tinkered
    1. (verbal particle)
    2.  
    1. (12)
    1. a.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. zur
    2. to the
    1. Werkstatt
    2. garage
    1. gefahren.
    2. ridden
    1. (mitadv)
    2.  
    1. ‘Ben belonged to a set of people riding to the garage.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. zur
    2. to the
    1. Werkstatt
    2. garage
    1. mitgefahren.
    2. with:ridden
    1. (verbal particle)
    2.  
    1. (13)
    1. a.
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. sprang
    2. jumps
    1. {mit
    2. {mitadv
    1. [ʔ]auf
    2. up
    1. /
    2. /
    1. *mitauf}.
    2. with:up}
    1. (mitadv)
    2.  
    1. ‘Mia belonged to a set of people jumping up.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. läuft
    2. runs
    1. {*vor
    2. {forward
    1. [ʔ]an
    2. at
    1. /
    2. /
    1. voran}.
    2. forward:at}
    1. (verbal particle)
    2.  
    1. ‘Mia is running ahead.’

Second, I will ignore object-oriented examples, as in (14). Here, the implicit participant is an alternative to the entity in object position.

    1. (14)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. stellt
    2. puts
    1. das
    2. the
    1. Rad
    2. bike
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. in
    2. in
    1. den
    2. the
    1. Flur.
    2. hall
    1. ‘Ben is putting the bike in the hall, which accompanies Ben’s putting at least one other thing in the hall.’

It is a reasonable working hypothesis that, in principle, the interpretation is analogous to the standard subject-oriented case. However, the implementation of the different orientation is a compositional challenge in its own right, which I will leave for another occasion.

Third, I will confine the discussion to free mit in German. Except for English, other Germanic languages have a comparable free particle as well; see Hoekstra (2004) for a brief overview that takes the situation in Frisian as a starting point. However, the particle’s distribution is not exactly the same across languages. The detailed discussion of the German case might be inspiring for a better understanding of the facts in the other languages, but a proper comparison will be left to future work.

The paper is structured as follows: in Section 2, I will provide a survey of the core descriptive properties of mitadv, which is followed by the sketch of a formal analysis in Section 3. Section 4 is concerned with the opposition between a constructional and a compositional approach to mitsup. Based on a general discussion of free mit within stative predications, I propose a uniform entry for mitfree and spell out its application to the various stative predications. Section 5 offers a conclusion.

2 Adverbial mit: Survey of descriptive properties

2.1 Focus sensitivity

I will start with some general background information on the interpretation of additives. According to standard assumptions (usually building on the analysis of only and even in Horn 1969; see Sudhoff 2010 for an overview), auch is an additive focus particle that conveys a bipartite interpretation as sketched in (16) for the example in (15); recall (3) from the introduction.

    1. (15)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. AUCH
    2. also
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘Ben is ALso tinkering with a soapbox.’
(16) a. assertion: Ben is tinkering with a soapbox.
  b. presupposition: Someone different from Ben is tinkering with a soapbox.

One well-known trait is that the relevant alternative is determined by focus. For instance, if auch is located in the middlefield, the association with the subject in the prefield hinges on stressing auch, as in (15). Alternatively, the association can be made syntactically transparent by moving auch to the prefield as well, as in (17) (recall (4) from the introduction).

    1. (17)
    1. Auch
    2. also
    1. BEN
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox

If, by contrast, auch in the middlefield does not bear stress, or auch joins the verbal predication in the prefield, as in (18), the interpretation changes: Ben’s tinkering is now presupposed to relate to other things than a soapbox.

    1. (18)
    1. Auch
    2. also
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. SEIfenkiste
    2. soapbox
    1. basteln
    2. tinker
    1. wird
    2. will
    1. Ben.
    2. Ben
    1. ‘Ben will be tinkering also with a SOAPbox.’

Crucially, mitadv is not focus-sensitive in a comparable way. It cannot join the alleged focal expression in the prefield, as in (19) (recall (4)). Furthermore, the relevant alternative implication (the status of which will be discussed in the subsequent sections) unequivocally relates to the subject. Correspondingly, both (20) and (21) convey that Ben’s tinkering involves other agents, irrespective of the fact that mitadv does not bear stress in (20) and that it adjoins the verbal predication in the prefied in (21).4

    1. (19)
    1. *Mit
    2.   mitadv
    1. BEN
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. (20)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. SEIfenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. (21)
    1. Mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. SEIfenkiste
    2. soapbox
    1. basteln
    2. tinker
    1. wird
    2. will
    1. Ben.
    2. Ben
    1. ‘Ben will belong to a set of people tinkering with a SOAPbox.’

There is one further indication for the assumption that mitadv is independent of the focus-sensitive introduction of alternatives. Namely, its combination with true focus particles yields regular results. For instance, the addition of the additive auch in (22) is not redundant. Instead, the usual bipartite meaning contributed by the additive operates on top of the meaning contributed by mitadv; compare the rough interpretation of (22) in (23).5

    1. (22)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. fährt
    2. rides
    1. AUCH
    2. also
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. nach
    2. to
    1. Rom.
    2. Rome
    1. ‘Ben ALso belongs to a set of people riding to Rome.’
(23) a. assertion: Ben is joining a set of people riding to Rome.
  b. presupposition: Someone different from Ben is joining a set of people riding to Rome.

The same observation holds for the restrictive particle nur ‘only’. According to standard assumptions (again building on Horn 1969), nur x P contributes the assertion that nobody except for x P, and the presupposition that x P. This is exactly what can be observed for the combination with mitadv, as shown by (24) and its interpretation in (25).

    1. (24)
    1. Nur
    2. only
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. nach
    2. to
    1. Rom
    2. Rome
    1. gefahren.
    2. ridden
    1. ‘Only Ben belonged to a set of people riding to Rome.’
(25) a. assertion: Nobody except for Ben joined a set of people riding to Rome.
  b. presupposition: Ben joined a set of people riding to Rome.

The exclusion of alternatives by nur thus does not contradict the contribution made by mitadv: (24) still conveys that Ben must not be the only one who took a ride to Rome. This suggests that the introduction of alternatives by mitadv differs from their introduction by focus-sensitive items.6

I conclude that mitadv is not focus-sensitive. Instead, it forms a regular constituent with the right-hand verbal predication. This argues against Bücker’s (2012) treatment of mitadv as an additive particle.

2.2 The semantic-pragmatic status of the accompaniment relation and the alternative implication

This section is concerned with the content contributed by mitadv and its semantic-pragmatic status. The hypothesis is that mitadv introduces an accompaniment of an implicit eventuality by participation in a corresponding eventuality; recall the paraphrase in (5), repeated in (26b).

(26) a. Ben bastelt mit an einer Seifenkiste.
  b. Ben is accompanying an implicit tinkering with a soapbox by himself tinkering with the soapbox.

This predicts differences from both auch and mit-PPs: auch does not convey an accompaniment (irrespective of the fact that it does not exclude it), and the alternative is not merely implicit, but presupposed. Examples based on mit-PPs such as (27) are also different: they introduce the alternative explicitly; what is more, they associate the co-participant with the internal argument of mit, but not with the subject, as mitadv according to (26b) does.

    1. (27)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘Ben is tinkering with a soapbox together with Mia.’

Before testing the given hypothesis by various semantic-pragmatic diagnostics, a very general constraint on the interpretation of mitadv must be made explicit. It is well known that mit-PPs license a fairly broad range of interpretations; see Seiler (1974), Strigin (1995), and Rapoport (2014). In addition to the so-called comitative use exemplified in (27), the mit-PP can introduce an instrument or a manner, as in (28), or a concomitant circumstance, as in (29). Furthermore, it can also fill argument(like) slots, as in (30). (This list is focused on the verbal domain and is not exhaustive; see Seiler 1974: (27i), (10i), (29i), (37i) for similar examples.)

    1. (28)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. {mit
    2. {with
    1. seinem
    2. his
    1. neuen
    2. new
    1. Werkzeug
    2. tool
    1. /
    2. /
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. Sorgfalt}
    2. care}
    1. an
    2. with
    1. Mias
    2. Mia’s
    1. Rad.
    2. bike
    1. ‘Ben is tinkering with Mia’s bike {with his new tool / with care}.’
    1. (29)
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. fährt
    2. rides
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Dämmerung
    2. dawn
    1. in
    2. to
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Stadt.
    2. town
    1. ‘Mia is riding to town at dawn.’
    1. (30)
    1. Paul
    2. Paul
    1. füllt
    2. fills
    1. das
    2. the
    1. Glas
    2. glass
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. Murmeln.
    2. marbles
    1. ‘Paul is filling the glass with marbles.’

It is obvious that mitadv cannot receive any of these readings. For instance, the examples with mitadv in (31) cannot receive an instrument reading.

    1. (31)
    1. a.
    1.   Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. Mias
    2. Mia’s
    1. Rad.
    2. bike
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. #Das
    2.   the
    1. neue
    2. new
    1. Werkzeug
    2. tool
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. Mias
    2. Mia’s
    1. Rad.
    2. bike

This foundational constraint on the interpretation of mitadv shows that the explicit subject and the implicit participants must share their participant roles in relation to the verbal predication. This constraint is a first clear piece of evidence against an ellipsis account of mitadv; at least there is no obvious reason why the silent constituent should unequivocally introduce a co-participant of the subject argument. Notably, there are elliptical examples; see (32) (building on Strigin 1995: (4), Zifonun 1996/1997: (23a)). These, however, should not be conflated with mitadv-based examples. For one, the example in (32b) enforces the introduction of a suitable antecedent in the preceding context, as in (32a); furthermore, this mit can be coordinated with ohne ‘without’, which does not have a true free use.

    1. (32)
    1. a.
    1. [context: Mia and Paul are arguing about whether Ben was wearing his bathing cap while swimming to an isle.]
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Und
    2. and
    1. nun?
    2. now
    1. Ist
    2. is
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. oder
    2. or
    1. ohne
    2. without
    1. zur
    2. to the
    1. Insel
    2. isle
    1. geschwommen?
    2. swum
    1. ‘Well then? Did Ben swim to the isle with or without the bathing cap?’

The only candidate for a serious comparison to mitadv then is the comitative use of mit-PPs.7 As already suggested above, I will however argue that even these two uses are not the same.

2.2.1 Projection tests

I will first test the accompaniment relation and the alternative implication for their projection properties. In their overview of projective contents, Tonhauser et al. (2013) argue that the standard family-of-sentence diagnostic for projective content (Chierchia & McConnell-Ginet 1990) should be applied in different ways depending on whether an expression is subject to so-called Strong Contextual Felicity or not. Let us therefore start with the latter. Strong Contextual Felicity tests whether a content is strongly presupposed, that is, whether it must be contextually given and cannot be accommodated. The example in (33a) shows that auch is at odds with a context that does not introduce an explicit alternative; auch is thus subject to Strong Contextual Felicity. (This is also the standard assumption for the additive too in English; see Tonhauser et al. 2013.) The example in (33b) shows that mitadv is different. The alternative implication (‘Someone different from the bus driver is working on a broken-down car.’) is compatible with the given context and thus not subject to Strong Contextual Felicity. The same is true for the accompaniment relation (‘The bus driver is accompanying an implicit working on a broken-down car.’), which need not be introduced before either. In other words, while auch introduces strong presuppositions, mitadv does not.

    1. (33)
    1. [context: A is sitting in a bus. The bus driver has left the bus; A does not know what is happening outside. B comes in and says:]
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. #Der
    2.   the
    1. Busfahrer
    2. bus driver
    1. schraubt
    2. screws
    1. AUCH
    2. also
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einem
    2. a
    1. kaputten
    2. broken-down
    1. Auto.
    2. car
    1. ‘The bus driver is ALso working on a broken-down car.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Der
    2. the
    1. Busfahrer
    2. bus driver
    1. schraubt
    2. screws
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einem
    2. a
    1. kaputten
    2. broken-down
    1. Auto.
    2. car
    1. ‘The bus driver belongs to a set of people working on a broken-down car.’

With this distinction in place, we can turn to the family-of-sentence diagnostic. According to this diagnostic, only projective content survives if it is embedded under family-of-sentence variants such as modals, conditionals, or negation. As mitadv is not subject to Strong Contextual Felicity, the relevant variants need not be contextualized in a particular way. The examples in (34) then show that the accompaniment is clearly not projective: None of the examples conveys that Ben is accompanying an implicit tinkering with a soapbox.

    1. (34)
    1. a.
    1. Es
    2. it
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. unmöglich,
    2. impossible
    1. dass
    2. that
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste
    2. soapbox
    1. bastelt;
    2. tinkers;
    1. er
    2. he
    1. hasst
    2. hates
    1. jede
    2. every
    1. Form
    2. kind
    1. von
    2. of
    1. Teamarbeit.
    2. teamwork
    1. ‘It is impossible that Ben belongs to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox; he hates all kinds of teamwork.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Wenn
    2. if
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste
    2. soapbox
    1. bastelt,
    2. tinkers
    1. kann
    2. can
    1. sich
    2. REFL
    1. das
    2. the
    1. entsprechende
    2. corresponding
    1. Team
    2. team
    1. freuen;
    2. rejoice
    1. er
    2. he
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. ein
    2. a
    1. echter
    2. true
    1. Kenner.
    2. expert
    1. ‘If Ben belongs to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox, the team in question can rejoice; he is a true expert.’
    1.  
    1. c.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. nicht
    2. not
    1. (bloß)
    2. (merely)
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste,
    2. soapbox
    1. sondern
    2. but
    1. er
    2. he
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. daran
    2. allein.
    1. with it
    2. alone
    1. ‘Ben does not (merely) belong to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox, but he is tinkering with it on his own.’

Furthermore, as the accompaniment requires that there are alternatives, the alternative implication does not project either; see (35).

    1. (35)
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. nicht
    2. not
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. fliegenden
    2. flying
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. An
    2. with
    1. so
    2. such a
    1. etwas
    2. thing
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. niemand!
    2. nobody
    1. ‘Mia does not belong to a set of people tinkering with a flying soapbox. Nobody tinkers with such a thing!’

The situation for auch is again not the same. The family-of-sentence diagnostic shows that the alternative presupposition associated with auch is projective (see Tonhauser et al. 2013 for the same claim regarding the additive too in English). For instance, in (36), it survives the embedding under a modal and is therefore at variance with the given context.8

    1. (36)
    1. a.
    1.   [context: A and B are talking about hobbies of their friends; they have not yet talked about tinkering with soapboxes. They know Ben as being a tinkerer. A says:]
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. #Es
    2.   it
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. möglich,
    2. possible
    1. dass
    2. that
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. AUCH
    2. also
    1. an
    2. with
    1. Seifenkisten
    2. soapboxes
    1. bastelt.
    2. tinkers
    1. ‘It is possible that Ben ALso tinkers with soapboxes.’

Tonhauser et al. (2013) discuss the so-called Obligatory Local Effect as a third diagnostic for projective content. It tests whether a (projective) content must scope under an embedding operator such as glauben ‘believe’ (see also Gazdar 1979; Potts 2005). auch and mitadv are both subject to the Obligatory Local Effect and thus do not contrast here. However, this commonality can be used in order to reveal that both expressions introduce different propositional contents; compare (37).

    1. (37)
    1.   [context: Ben is tinkering with a soapbox with Mia. Paul knows about the people tinkering with a soapbox; however, he does not know anything about a cooperation.]
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. #Paul
    2.   Paul
    1. glaubt,
    2. believes
    1. dass
    2. that
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste
    2. soapbox
    1. bastelt.
    2. tinkers
    1. ‘Paul believes that Ben belongs to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1.   Paul
    2.   Paul
    1. glaubt,
    2. believes
    1. dass
    2. that
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. AUCH
    2. also
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste
    2. soapbox
    1. bastelt.
    2. tinkers
    1. ‘Paul believes that Ben is ALso tinkering with a soapbox.’

By hypothesis, mitadv involves an accompaniment by participation; therefore, a context that negates any knowledge of a cooperation by the attitude holder is incompatible with a belief report to the contrary. This is different for auch. By hypothesis, it is not bound to an accompaniment; therefore, the given context is compatible with the given belief report.

In sum, all three projection tests reveal clear differences between mitadv and auch: in contrast to auch, mitadv introduces neither strong presuppositions nor projective content. Furthermore, only mitadv contributes an accompaniment by participation.

2.2.2 Tests for discourse transparency

Although both the accompaniment and the alternative implication as introduced by mitadv are not projective, they do not share the same semantic-pragmatic status. In particular, according to (26b), the accompaniment is identified as explicit content, whereas the host situation including its participants is identified as merely implicit content. This suggests that only the former is discourse-transparent and thus a potential target for anaphors, cross-sentential operators, and explicit questions; see Farkas & de Swart (2003); Potts (2005); Amaral et al. (2007); Jayez (2010); Tonhauser (2012) for elaborate discussions of these diagnostics.

The example in (38) shows that mitadv does not license a pronominal anaphor to the alternatives or to the relevant team. Similarly, the anaphor das ‘that’ in (39) can relate to Mia’s accompaniment by participation, but not to the cooperation as such.

    1. (38)
    1. #Mia
    2.   Mia
    1. schraubt
    2. screws
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einem
    2. a
    1. Bentley.
    2. Bentley
    1. Sie
    2. they
    1. treffen
    2. meet
    1. sich
    2. REFL
    1. montags.
    2. Mondays.
    1.   ‘Mia belongs to a set of people working on a Bentley. They meet on Mondays.’
    1. (39)
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. schraubt
    2. screws
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einem
    2. a
    1. Bentley.
    2. Bentley
    1. Das
    2. that
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. toll.
    2. great
    1. ‘Mia belongs to a set of people working on a Bentley. That (= her accompaniment / ≠ the cooperation) is great.’

Notably, given mitadv, corresponding anaphoric descriptions are feasible, as shown in (40). In contrast to pronouns, definite descriptions can convey indirect anaphors that lack an explicit antecedent. The examples thus support the assumption that mitadv introduces the relevant information implicitly.

    1. (40)
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. schraubt
    2. screws
    1. #(mit)
    2. (mitadv)
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einem
    2. a
    1. Bentley.
    2. Bentley
    1. ‘Mia belongs to a set of people working on a Bentley.’
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. {Das
    2. {the
    1. Team
    2. team
    1. /
    2. /
    1. Die
    2. the
    1. Teamarbeit}
    2. teamwork}
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. toll.
    2. great
    1. ‘{The team / The teamwork} is great.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Die
    2. the
    1. Partner
    2. partners
    1. sind
    2. are
    1. sehr
    2. very
    1. kompetent.
    2. competent
    1. ‘The partners are very competent.’

The example in (41) shows that mitadv licenses operator attachment to the accompaniment. Ben’s preference for working on his own is a plausible reason against his accompaniment of a tinkering with a soapbox. Therefore, the use of mitadv in the matrix clause is compatible with a concessive adverbial, but incompatible with a causal one.

    1. (41)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste,
    2. soapbox
    1. {obwohl
    2. {although
    1. /
    2. /
    1. #weil}
    2. because}
    1. er
    2. he
    1. gern
    2. gladly
    1. für
    2. for
    1. sich
    2. himself
    1. arbeitet.
    2. works
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox {although / because} he likes to work on his own.’

By contrast, operators cannot attach to the alternative implication, as shown in (42). Notably, the context provides candidates for relevant alternatives; that is, although beide ‘both’ within the adverbial clause refers to Lilli and Mia, the adverbial cannot relate to their participation in the tinkering. This argues against an ellipsis account of mitadv: if there were a silent internal argument of the preposition that could be recovered from the context, (42) should be fine.

    1. (42)
    1. #Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. sich
    2. REFL
    1. gestern
    2. yesterday
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. Lilli
    2. Lilli
    1. und
    2. and
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. getroffen.
    2. met
    1. Er
    2. he
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste
    2. soapbox
    1. gebastelt,
    2. tinkered
    1. weil
    2. because
    1.  
    2.  
    1. beide
    2. both
    1. gerne
    2. gladly
    1. basteln.
    2. tinker
    1. ‘Ben met Lilli and Mia yesterday. He belonged to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox because both like to tinker.’

Finally, the given picture is corroborated by question-answer pairs. The examples in (43) show that mitadv supports answers to questions that are sensitive to an accompaniment. It is noteworthy that mitadv can be contrasted with allein ‘alone’; this can only be explained if mitadv is the bearer of the relevant accompaniment.9

    1. (43)
    1. a.
    1. Beteiligt
    2. participates
    1. sich
    2. REFL
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. an
    2. in
    1. einem
    2. a
    1. Basteln
    2. tinkering
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste?
    2. soapbox
    1. – Ja,
    2. – yes
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘Does Ben participate in a tinkering with a soapbox? – Yes, Ben belongs to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. alLEIN
    2. alone
    1. an
    2. with
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Seifenkiste?
    2. soapbox
    1. – Nein,
    2. – no
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. nur
    2. only
    1. MIT
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘Does Ben tinker with the soapbox aLONE? – No, Ben only belongs to a SET of people tinkering with the soapbox.’

The examples in (44) show that questions that are sensitive to the alternative implication are not feasible. Note that the question provides explicit potential alternatives; their inaccessibility is again at odds with an ellipsis account of mitadv.

    1. (44)
    1. #Was
    2.   what
    1. tun
    2. do
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. und
    2. and
    1. Lilli?
    2. Lilli
    1. – Ben
    2. – Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1.   ‘What are Mia and Lilli doing? – Ben belongs to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox.’

In sum, the diagnostics show that mitadv involves a discourse-transparent accompaniment and a discourse-opaque alternative implication.

Let me conclude this subsection with a brief comparison to mit-PPs. They support anaphors to alternatives, the attachment of alternative-sensitive operators, and answers to alternative-sensitive questions; see the contrast between (45) and (38), (42), (44).

    1. (45)
    1. a.
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. schraubt
    2. screws
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. anderen
    2. others
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einem
    2. a
    1. Bentley.
    2. Bentley
    1. Sie
    2. they
    1. treffen
    2. meet
    1. sich
    2. REFL
    1. montags.
    2. Mondays
    1. ‘Mia works on a Bentley with others. They meet on Mondays.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. sich
    2. REFL
    1. gestern
    2. yesterday
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. Lilli
    2. Lilli
    1. und
    2. and
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. getroffen.
    2. met
    1. Er
    2. he
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. ihnen
    2. them
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste
    2. soapbox
    1. gebastelt,
    2. tinkered
    1. weil
    2. because
    1. beide
    2. both
    1. gerne
    2. gladly
    1. basteln.
    2. tinker
    1. ‘Ben met Lilli and Mia yesterday. He was tinkering with a soapbox with them because both like to tinker.’
    1.  
    1. c.
    1. Was
    2. what
    1. tun
    2. do
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. und
    2. and
    1. Lilli?
    2. Lilli
    1. – Ben
    2. – Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. ihnen
    2. them
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘What are Mia and Lilli doing? – Ben is tinkering with a soapbox with them.’

This is as expected, given that the relevant alternatives are explicit here. Recall, however, that the contrasting behavior of mitadv does not follow from an ellipsis account; the examples in (42) and (44) above show that mitadv does not introduce analogous silent slots for PP-internal arguments. This is a clear difference between mit-PPs and mitadv. In the next section, I will argue that the involved accompaniment relations differ as well. The difference in interpretation between the example in (43b) with mitadv and the analogous example with a mit-PP in (46) is already suggestive of a distinction.

    1. (46)
    1. Bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. alLEIN
    2. alone
    1. an
    2. with
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Seifenkiste?
    2. soapbox
    1. – Nein,
    2. – no
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. nur
    2. only
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. Lilli
    2. Lilli
    1. und
    2. and
    1. MIa
    2. Mia
    1. an
    2. with
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘Does Ben tinker with the soapbox aLONE? – No, Ben only tinkers with the soapbox with Lilli and MIa.’

In (43b), mitadv conveys that Ben is playing only an accompanying role in the tinkering. In (46), however, the mit-PP conveys a condition; it says that Ben is tinkering with the soapbox only if Mia and Lilli accompany him. That is, the forced contrast to allein ‘alone’ shows that the roles are reversed.

2.2.3 Accompaniment by participation: Adverbial mit vs. prepositional mit

With regard to mit-PPs such as (47), Seiler (1974: 235) writes that “it is precisely the function of the Comitative […] to leave unspecified the extent of participation in the action”; see also Strigin (1995: 320) and Rapoport (2014: 161).

    1. (47)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘Ben is tinkering with a soapbox with Mia.’

Accordingly, this example does not specify whether Mia and Ben are coequal agents or whether Mia is accompanying Ben’s tinkering without tinkering herself (in Strigin’s words, she could just be being cheerful). How does mitadv fit into this picture?

The continuations (48a) and (48b) in (48) show that mitadv does not specify the extent of participation either.

    1. (48)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox.’
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. Allerdings
    2. however
    1. trägt
    2. contributes
    1. er
    2. he
    1. nur
    2. only
    1. wenig
    2. little
    1. bei.
    2. to
    1. ‘However, he only is contributing little to it.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Tatsächlich
    2. in fact
    1. macht
    2. does
    1. er
    2. he
    1. das
    2. the
    1. meiste.
    2. most
    1. ‘In fact, he is doing the most.’

However, there are two crucial differences from mit-PPs. First, the co-participant the varying contribution of whom is under consideration in (48) is the subject argument. This comes to light most clearly in cases that make an asymmetric interpretation prominent; see (49) and (50).

    1. (49)
    1. a.
    1. [context: Ben is listening to a concert on the radio; Mia is in the concert.]
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. {Ben
    2. {Ben
    1. /
    2. /
    1. #Mia}
    2. Mia}
    1. hörte
    2. listens
    1. das
    2. the
    1. Konzert
    2. concert
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an.
    2. to
    1. ‘{Ben / Mia} belonged to a set of people listening to the concert.’
    1. (50)
    1. a.
    1. [context: The speaker knows that Mia will be traveling to Canada and that Ben has decided spontaneously to join her.]
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. {Ben
    2. {Ben
    1. /
    2. /
    1. #Mia}
    2. Mia}
    1. reist
    2. travels
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. nach
    2. to
    1. Kanada.
    2. Canada
    1. ‘{Ben / Mia} will belong to a set of people traveling to Canada.’

This reversal of argument assignments provides clear evidence against an ellipsis account of mitadv: the co-participant is not introduced as an implicit internal argument of a putative mit-PP.

Second, the co-participant as introduced by mitadv is related more closely to the explicit event description than the co-participant as introduced by a mit-PP is. Most notably, examples based on mitadv entail that the event predication is predicated of the subject argument; recall the entailment in (51) (= (8b)). (Qualifications of this observation will be discussed in Section 3.) This is different for mit-PPs such as mit Mia in (47). As said, Mia could just be cheerful and would thus not be an agent of the relevant eventuality.

    1. (51)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1.  
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox

This difference can be conceived of as a natural byproduct of the fact that mitadv promotes the co-participant to the subject position. In other words, the subject is not just a ‘comitative’ to an independent event; instead, mitadv brings about the introduction of a separate event that accompanies an implicit host event. The accompaniment conveyed by mitadv thus does not relate participants to events, but rather events of the same kind to each other. I suppose that this is also the reason why only mitadv is sensitive to asymmetric interpretations. For instance, even in a context as given in (50), a mit-PP can be used for the primary participant, as in (52).

    1. (52)
    1. a.
    1. [context: The speaker knows that Mia will be traveling to Canada and that Ben has decided spontaneously to join her.]
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. reist
    2. travels
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. nach
    2. to
    1. Kanada.
    2. Canada
    1. ‘Ben will be traveling to Canada with Mia.’

The proposed distinction between comitatives on the one hand and accompaniment by participation on the other can explain this as follows. With mit-PPs, the particular justification of the comitative role is left fully unspecified; with mitadv, by contrast, it is the co-participant’s participation as such that is marked as an accompaniment.

I conclude that mitadv is clearly different from mit-PPs and thus not elliptical. It introduces a participation in an eventuality that is conceived of as accompanying an eventuality of the same kind.

2.3 Interim conclusions

I have argued for the following key traits of mitadv. It is not focus-sensitive, but a regular modifier to the verbal projection; as such, it induces the explicit subject to accompany a host eventuality by participation in a corresponding eventuality. More specifically, the introduced accompaniment is identified as explicit content. It is neither presupposed nor projective, but discourse-transparent and thus accessible to cross-sentential anaphors, operators, and questions. The host eventuality including its alternative participants is identified as implicit content. While this content is neither presupposed nor projective either, it is discourse-opaque and thus inaccessible to anaphors, cross-sentential operators, and questions.

I conclude that mitadv can be neither an additive such as auch ‘also’ (which, for instance, is focus-sensitive and lacks any explicit information about an accompaniment) nor a PP with a retrievable internal argument (which, for instance, supports contextual accessibility of co-participants and does not enforce that the subject receives an accompanying role). The overview of descriptive properties thus very clearly calls for a new proposal, which I will tackle next.

3 Adverbial mit: Analysis

In order to sketch a formal analysis of mitadv, I make two simplified assumptions. First, following Farkas & de Swart (2003), I distinguish between discourse-transparent ‘normal’ discourse referents on the one hand and discourse-opaque variables on the other. The basic idea is that discourse-opaque variables depend on predicative content, but lack referential force; one prime example is implicit arguments. For instance, a passive such as The problem was solved does not introduce an explicit agent; nevertheless, the underlying predicate solve still entails the existence of a corresponding implicit entity. For the purposes of the present paper, I will not dwell on an appropriate formal model of this distinction, but merely use it for a representation of the distinction between discourse-transparent explicit arguments and discourse-opaque implicit ones; the latter are identified by the subscript i (which stands for implicit).10 Second, I assume that the domain of entities is structured in terms of ontologically different types. Specifically, I will use e, ei, etc. for eventualities, s, si, etc. for states, and r, ri, etc. for so-called tropes (more on this less familiar type in Section 4.2.1). I do not associate the variables x, xi, y, yi, etc. with specific types; instead, I assume that they either represent entities of some general type or that their specific typing can be read off the predicates they are related to. Furthermore, I will use ‘≤’ and ‘≰’ for the relations ‘is part of’ and ‘is not part of’, respectively. I take for granted that these part relations are relativized appropriately to the types of entities they relate; for instance, if ‘≤’ relates two individuals, it introduces a part relation on individuals, if ‘≤’ relates two events, it introduces a part relation on events, etc. (see, for instance, Lasersohn 1998).

Based on these ingredients, I propose the following meaning representation for mitadv.

(53) ⟦mitadv⟧ = λPλxλeeixi[P(x)(e) ∧ P(xi)(ei) ∧ accomp′(e, ei) ∧ xxieei]

According to (53), mitadv modifies a predication of eventualities in such a way that the predication is distributed over a discourse-transparent explicit eventuality and a distinct discourse-opaque implicit eventuality (where each predication includes its respective highest-ranked participant role). The variable for the explicit eventuality is compositionally active, while the variable for the implicit eventuality is existentially closed. Furthermore, both eventualities are related to each other by accomp′, for which I propose the following truth conditions:

(54) For any eventualities e, e′: accomp′(e, e′) = 1 iff (i) e and e′ form an integrated whole and (ii) e is an extension of e′.

Condition (i) builds on aspects of the analysis of adverbial ‘together’ in Moltmann (2004). The key idea is that the parts of an integrated whole share relevant properties that are not shared by entities that are not part of the integrated whole. The choice of relevant properties depends on the type of entities that form the integrated whole and on perspective. For eventualities, spatio-temporal contiguity and the sharing of participants is particularly relevant (a further option is discussed below). Condition (ii) is about the different roles e and e′ play within the integrated whole. The key idea here is that e′ provides a spatio-temporal structure that can host e as an additional concomitant component. Crudely put, e is parasitic on e′. Notably, this does not say that e is necessarily less important than e′; it merely says that one conceives of e as the part that secondarily joins e′.

The resultant compositional derivation for the example in (55) is fully regular. The combination of mitadv with the verbal predication yields the representation in (56); the subsequent integration of the subject and the binding of the explicit eventuality yield the truth conditions in (57) for the sentence as a whole.

    1. (55)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people tinkering with a soapbox.’
(56) ⟦mit an einer Seifenkiste basteln⟧
  = ⟦mitadv⟧(⟦an einer Seifenkiste basteln⟧)
  = [λPλxλeeixi[P(x)(e) ∧ P(xi)(ei) ∧ accomp′(e, ei) ∧ xxieei]]
(λxλeb[tinker-with′(e) ∧ ag′(e, x) ∧ th′(e, b) ∧ soapbox′(b)])
  = λxλeeixi[∃b[tinker-with′(e) ∧ ag′(e, x) ∧ th′(e, b) ∧ soapbox′(b)] ∧
b[tinker-with′(ei) ∧ ag′(ei, xi) ∧ th′(ei, b) ∧ soapbox′(b)] ∧ accomp′(e, ei) ∧ xxi ∧ e ≰ ei]
(57) ⟦Ben bastelt mit an einer Seifenkiste⟧
  = 1 iff ∃eeixi[∃b[tinker-with′(e) ∧ ag′(e, Ben) ∧ th′(e, b) ∧ soapbox′(b)]
∧ ∃b[tinker-with′(ei) ∧ ag′(ei, xi) ∧ th′(ei, b) ∧ soapbox′(b)] ∧ accomp′(e, ei)
∧ Ben ≰ xi ∧ e ≰ ei]

In prose: (57) is true iff there is a tinkering with a soapbox by Ben and an implicit tinkering with a soapbox by at least one implicit other person such that Ben’s tinkering is the accompanying part of the integrated joint tinkering consisting of both tinkerings. This result captures the key traits of mitadv: Ben’s accompaniment of a tinkering with a soapbox by himself tinkering with a soapbox is identified as the explicit discourse-transparent content and thus predicted to be accessible to anaphors, operators, and questions. By contrast, the tinkering with a soapbox by some alternative is identified as implicit discourse-opaque content and thus predicted to be inaccessible to discourse-related operations. While mitadv thus introduces a distinction between explicit and implicit content, it does not introduce any presuppositions, as for instance auch would.

Furthermore, both tinkerings form an integrated whole with Ben’s tinkering as the additional concomitant part. This has three crucial consequences. First, the representation captures the asymmetry between both eventualities; in particular, it reverses and strengthens the role assignment of mit-PPs by assigning the accompanying role to the explicit subject and by enforcing its participation in the relevant eventuality as an agent and thus prohibiting pure concomitance. As desired, there are thus clear differences from the representation of a corresponding clause with an ordinary mit-PP, as in (58). According to (58), the accompanying part is contributed by the PP-internal referent, the assignment of a comitative role licenses pure concomitance, and the referent is explicit and thus discourse-transparent.

(58) ⟦Ben is tinkering with someone else with a soapbox.⟧
  = 1 iff ∃exb[tinker-with′(e) ∧ ag′(e, Ben) ∧ th′(e, b) ∧ soapbox′(b) ∧ comitative′(e, x) ∧ Ben ≰ x]

Second, the imposed integrity condition for accomp′ in (57) requires a justification: the implicit and the explicit tinkering should share time, location, and participants. This licenses the identification of the existentially closed soapboxes and thereby captures the intuition that—the distributive effect of mitadv notwithstanding—Ben and the implicit alternative are tinkering with the same soapbox. I have emphasized above that the particular criteria for integrity depend on the type of the conjoined entities and perspective. For instance, the example in (59) shows that the semantics should not require participant identification across the board.

    1. (59)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. raucht
    2. smokes
    1. eine
    2. a
    1. Zigarette
    2. cigarette
    1. mit.
    2. mitadv
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people smoking a cigarette.’

Our knowledge of smoking says that cigarettes are usually not shared and that spatio-temporal contiguity alone supports integrity. In fact, the integrity criteria are not set in stone for tinkering events either. For instance, let there be a soapbox competition where soapboxes are fabricated by single persons. One could use (55) here in order to indicate that Ben participates in the competition; integrity would not be achieved by the identity of the soapboxes, but by the common time, location, and purpose of the competition as a whole.

The third consequence relates to entailment patterns. Recall once more the entailment in (60) (= (8b), (51)). The entry in (53) predicts this veridicality effect of mitadv in a straightforward way; it simply follows from the distribution of the verbal predication.

    1. (60)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox
    1.  
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. bastelt
    2. tinkers
    1. an
    2. with
    1. einer
    2. a
    1. Seifenkiste.
    2. soapbox

However, there is a complication that has not yet been addressed. The examples in (61) (which I partly owe to an anonymous reviewer) show that not all predicates support veridicality (but see below for qualifications).

    1. (61)
    1. a.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. trug
    2. carried
    1. das
    2. the
    1. Klavier
    2. piano
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. hoch.
    2. up
    1.  
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. trug
    2. carried
    1. das
    2. the
    1. Klavier
    2. piano
    1. hoch.
    2. up
    1. ‘Ben belonged to a set of people carrying up the piano.’ ↛ ‘Ben carried up the piano.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. schließt
    2. closes
    1. das
    2. the
    1. Projekt
    2. project
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. ab.
    2. off
    1.  
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. schließt
    2. closes
    1. das
    2. the
    1. Projekt
    2. project
    1. ab.
    2. off
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people finishing the project.’ ↛ ‘Ben finishes the project.’
    1.  
    1. c.
    1. Der
    2. the
    1. Sessel
    2. armchair
    1. füllt
    2. fills
    1. den
    2. the
    1. Raum
    2. room
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. aus.
    2. out
    1.  
    1. Der
    2. the
    1. Sessel
    2. armchair
    1. füllt
    2. fills
    1. den
    2. the
    1. Raum
    2. room
    1. aus.
    2. out
    1. ‘The armchair belongs to a set of things filling out the room.’ ↛ ‘The armchair fills out the room.’

Intuitively, these predicates differ from the activity predicates discussed before by involving a causal effect that hinges on the joint contribution by all participants the predicate relates to. The predicates in (61a) and (61b) suggest that the change they involve depends on both the explicit agent and the implicit alternatives. Similarly, the achievement of maximal fullness as imposed by the stative ausfüllen ‘fill out’ in (61c) depends on the participants as a group. As my analysis of mitadv builds on joint participation, it is thus not surprising that the entailments in (61) are invalid. In fact, analogous findings are well known for comitatives (in the relevant co-subject reading) and collective interpretations of plurals; for instance, Ben carried up the piano with Paul and Ben and Paul carried up the piano do not entail that Ben carried up the piano; see Parsons (1990: 83), Moltmann (2004: Section 2), Lasersohn (2011: Section 4), and Schein (2017: Chapter 2). For reasons of space, I cannot provide a full-fledged formal treatment of these observations, but I will sketch a possible take on it in terms of the proposed analysis. The crucial ingredient is again the integrity condition. According to Moltmann (2004: 311–312), the integrity of a sum of parts can also be justified by the fact that the sum constitutes an entity of a particular type only in virtue of being a whole, that is, in virtue of being more than the sum of the parts. This integrity criterion is typical for predicates that involve a causal effect that depends on joint forces; see Moltmann’s own example: if two agents contribute to the solution of a problem, the sum of both contributions constitute a solving of a problem only in virtue of the fact that both contributions as a whole (not as individual contributions) yield the relevant change. I propose that this integrity criterion is at the heart of the entailment failures in (61); see the representation in (62).

(62) ⟦Ben hat das Klavier mit hochgetragen.⟧
  = 1 iff ∃eeixi[carry-up′(e) ∧ ag′(e, Ben) ∧ th′(e, ιp[piano′(p)]) ∧ carry-up′(ei) ∧ ag′(ei, xi) ∧ th′(ei, ιp[piano′(p)]) ∧ accomp′(e, ei) ∧ Ben ≰ xieei]

According to accomp′(e, ei) in (62), e and ei must form an integrated whole. In view of our knowledge about the carrying up of pianos, this strongly suggests that it is only this whole that constitutes an event of carrying up the piano. Therefore, e alone does not constitute such an eventuality, which predicts the entailment failure in (61a). A crucial formal consequence is that the distributed event predication in (62) must be understood in a loose activity sense such as ‘contribute to the carrying up of the piano’. Notably, this is in keeping with the intuition that, in this activity reading, the entailment in (61a) becomes valid.11

In the following, I will argue that this basic analysis of mitadv can be extended to a generalized version that also covers the use of free mit within superlative structures.

4 Generalizing free mit: Construction vs. composition

The example in (63) (= (6a)) again exemplifies the combination of free mit with the superlative (= mitsup).

    1. (63)
    1. In
    2. in
    1. diesem
    2. this
    1. Raum
    2. room
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. mit
    2. mitsup
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest
    1. ‘Ben belongs to the tallest ones in this room.’

Recall that Zifonun (1996/1997) and Bücker (2012) consider mitsup a separate construction that cannot be subsumed under their respective analyses for the adverbial counterpart. The uniqueness condition of the superlative would be at odds with a treatment of mitsup in terms of an additive or an elliptical PP; see (64) (= (7)). Furthermore, mitsup is generally not veridical; see (65) (= (8a)).

    1. (64)
    1. #Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. {auch
    2. {also
    1. /
    2. /
    1. mit
    2. with
    1. anderen}
    2. others}
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest
    1.   ‘Ben is {also / together with other people} the tallest.’
    1. (65)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitsup
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest
    1.  
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest

I will argue against this approach from two angles. To begin with, I will discuss the distributional properties of free mit within stative predications more generally. The observations will reveal substantial shortcomings of a constructional approach to mitsup. I will then show that the alternative proposal for mitadv developed above supports a generalized version that also covers mitsup. Crucially, this uniform compositional treatment will offer a promising systematic explanation for the specific distribution of free mit and interpretational effects such as (65).12

4.1 The distribution of free mit within stative predications

A first intriguing observation, already mentioned in the introduction, relates to the adjectival domain. In contrast to their counterparts in the superlative form, positive and comparative adjectives are typically incompatible with a free mit; see (66a) and (66b). (Qualifications of this assessment will be discussed in Sections 4.2.1 and 5.)

    1. (66)
    1. a.
    1. #Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. {groß
    2. {tall
    1. /
    2. /
    1. blond
    2. blond
    1. /
    2. /
    1. müde
    2. tired
    1. /
    2. /
    1. wütend}.
    2. angry}
    1.   ‘Ben belongs to a set of {tall / blond / tired / angry} people.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. #Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. {größer
    2. {taller
    1. /
    2. /
    1. müder
    2. more tired
    1. /
    2. /
    1. wütender}
    2. more angry}
    1. als
    2. than
    1. Mia.
    2. Mia
    1.   ‘Ben belongs to a set of people that are {taller / more tired / more angry} than Mia.’

This contrast seems to argue for a specific superlative construction that excludes other adjectival forms. But this approach does not explain why the putative alternative construction based on the adverbial mitadv is not felicitous either. Given the fine paraphrases in (66), there is no obvious explanation for the restriction. Furthermore, the examples in (67) show that a true additive is clearly compatible with both the positive and the comparative.

    1. (67)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. AUCH
    2. also
    1. {groß
    2. {tall
    1. /
    2. /
    1. größer
    2. taller
    1. als
    2. than
    1. Mia}.
    2. Mia}
    1. ‘Ben is ALso {tall / taller than Mia}.’

Second, free mit can be combined with locative PPs and APs, as in (68) and (69). (I owe (69) to an anonymous reviewer.)

    1. (68)
    1. a.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. {auf
    2. {in
    1. dem
    2. the
    1. Dachboden
    2. attic
    1. /
    2. /
    1. im
    2. in
    1. Keller}.
    2. the
    1.  
    2. basement}
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people {in the attic / in the basement}.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Der
    2. the
    1. Schlüssel
    2. key
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. in
    2. in
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Kiste.
    2. box
    1. ‘The key belongs to a set of things in the box.’
    1. (69)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. anwesend.
    2. present
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people present.’

This additional option shows that the use of free mit within copula structures is not limited to the superlative. Hence, either the constructional approach must posit yet another copula-based construction, or these examples have to be subsumed under the adverbial case (which would, however, make all the more puzzling why neither the positive nor the comparative in (66) can resort to this option).

A third observation relates to state expressions in general. Maienborn (2003; 2005) distinguishes between Kimian states and Davidsonian states. While K(imian)-states are conceived of as exemplifications of a property at a bearer (a conception based on Kim 1976), D(avidsonian)-states are conceived of as ordinary eventualities in the world (a conception based on Davidson 1967). As a consequence, only D-state verbs pass standard event diagnostics. For instance, direct perception reports are licensed by D-state verbs such as lie (stand, sleep, gleam, etc.), but not by K-state verbs such as resemble (love, weigh, belong to, etc.) and copula structures such as be in the box, which are taken to always convey K-states; see (70).

(70) Paul saw {the key lie in the box / #Mia resemble her sister / #the key be in the box}.

Maienborn (2003: Chapter 6) also discusses the distribution of comitative mit-PPs as one further diagnostic. She argues that K-states are generally at odds with participants and thus incompatible with comitatives. However, according to the above findings, free mit is partially compatible with K-state denoting copula structures. I therefore conclude that the distinction between K-states and D-states as such cannot be the ultimate crucial factor. In Section 4.2, I will argue that it is rather the type of the underlying predication—that is, the content of the predicative AP, DP, or PP—that determines the distribution of free mit. This refined perspective on the role of K-states as opposed to D-states is also reflected in the distribution of mitadv. K-state verbs such as ähneln ‘resemble’, 70 kg wiegen ‘weigh 70 kg’, and lieben ‘love’ are in fact infelicitous with mitadv, as shown by (71a). However, a K-state verb such as gehören zu ‘belong to’ is felicitous with mitadv, as shown by (71b).

    1. (71)
    1. a.
    1. #Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. {ähnelt
    2. {resembles
    1. Tim
    2. Tim
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. /
    2. /
    1. wiegt
    2. weighs
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. 70 kg
    2. 70 kg
    1. /
    2. /
    1. liebt
    2. loves
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. mit}.
    2. mitadv}
    1.   ‘Ben belongs to a set of people that {resemble Tim / weigh 70 kg / love Mia}.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1.   Dies
    2.   this
    1. gehört
    2. belongs
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. zu
    2. to
    1. unseren
    2. our
    1. Aufgaben.
    2. tasks
    1.   ‘This belongs to a set of things that are our tasks.’

This suggests that the constraint in (71a) is not rooted in the K-state as such, but in the underlying content as provided by the lexical verb. D-state verbs do not behave in a uniform way either. Locative D-state verbs such as stehen ‘stand’ or liegen ‘lie’ license mitadv if the locative component is made explicit. This can be achieved either by a prepositional locative, as in (72), or by an adjective that makes a locative relation prominent, as in (73). (I owe (73) to an anonymous reviewer.)

    1. (72)
    1. a.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. an
    2. at
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Ecke.
    2. corner
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people standing at the corner.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Der
    2. the
    1. Schlüssel
    2. key
    1. liegt
    2. lies
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. in
    2. in
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Kiste.
    2. box
    1. ‘The key belongs to a set of things lying in the box.’
    1. (73)
    1. Das
    2. the
    1. Kalb
    2. calf
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. schattig,
    2. shadily
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Mutterkuh
    2. mother cow
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. schattig.
    2. shadily
    1. ‘The calf is standing in the shade, and the mother cow belongs to a set of entities standing in the shade.’

However, once the locative component is dropped such that a position mode interpretation is enforced, the use of mitadv becomes infelicitous, as in (74) (see Kaufmann 1995: 98–120 for a general discussion of the distinction between a locative and a position mode component within the lexical semantics of locative verbs). The D-state verb schlafen ‘sleep’ provides an analogous minimal pair, as in (75). Finally, D-state verbs that introduce a specific mode of sensory perception such as glänzen ‘gleam’ or duften ‘smell’ are also at odds with mitadv, as shown in (76).13

    1. (74)
    1. #Das
    2.   the
    1. Kalb
    2. calf
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. schon,
    2. already
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Mutterkuh
    2. mother cow
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. mit.
    2. mitadv
    1.   ‘The calf is already standing, and the mother cow belongs to a set of entities standing.’
    1. (75)
    1. a.
    1.   Das
    2.   the
    1. Kind
    2. child
    1. schläft
    2. sleeps
    1. in
    2. in
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Hängematte,
    2. hammock
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Katze
    2. cat
    1. schläft
    2. sleeps
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. in
    2. in
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Hängematte.
    2. hammock
    1. ‘The child is sleeping in the hammock, and the cat belongs to a set of entities sleeping in the hammock.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. #Das
    2.   the
    1. Kind
    2. child
    1. schläft,
    2. sleeps
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Katze
    2. cat
    1. schläft
    2. sleeps
    1. mit.
    2. mitadv
    1.   ‘The child is sleeping, and the cat belongs to a set of entities sleeping.’
    1. (76)
    1. a.
    1. #Der
    2.   the
    1. Teller
    2. plate
    1. glänzte,
    2. gleamed
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Tasse
    2. cup
    1. glänzte
    2. gleamed
    1. mit.
    2. mitadv
    1.   ‘The plate was gleaming, and the cup belonged to a set of entities gleaming.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. #Die
    2.   the
    1. Tulpe
    2. tulip
    1. duftete
    2. smelled
    1. süßlich,
    2. sweet
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Rose
    2. rose
    1. duftete
    2. smelled
    1. mit
    2. mitadv
    1. süßlich.
    2. sweet
    1.   ‘The tulip had a sweet scent, and the rose belonged to a set of entities having a sweet scent.’

Given these fine-grained distinctions, an adequate explanation for the distribution of mitadv cannot rely on the contrast between K-state verbs and D-state verbs as such, but must be sensitive to their underlying predications. Irrespective of such an explanation, it is unclear how the constructional approach to free mit can account for the constraints. Obviously, the adverbial case would have to be split into possible and impossible construction types as well. Furthermore, auch is not sensitive to any of these restrictions, as shown by (77); this renders the approach by Bücker (2012) a non-starter.

    1. (77)
    1. a.
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. {ähnelt
    2. {resembles
    1. Tim
    2. Tim
    1. AUCH
    2. also
    1. /
    2. /
    1. wiegt
    2. weighs
    1. AUCH
    2. also
    1. 70 kg}.
    2. 70 kg}
    1. ‘Ben {ALso resembles Tim / ALso weighs 70 kg}.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Das
    2. the
    1. Kalb
    2. calf
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. schon,
    2. already
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Mutterkuh
    2. mother cow
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. AUCH.
    2. also
    1. ‘The calf is already standing, and the mother cow is ALso standing.’
    1.  
    1. c.
    1. Der
    2. the
    1. Teller
    2. plate
    1. glänzte,
    2. gleamed
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Tasse
    2. cup
    1. glänzte
    2. gleamed
    1. AUCH.
    2. also
    1. ‘The plate was gleaming, and the cup was ALso gleaming.’

I conclude that the constructional approach to mitsup and mitadv runs the risk of a proliferation of construction types without advancing any systematic explanation for relevant constraints. Building on the analysis of mitadv in Section 3, the following section will spell out a generalized compositional proposal for free mit that complies with such an explanation.

4.2 Generalizing the composition of free mit

According to the analysis in Section 3, mitadv relates eventualities to each other. A generalized version is provided in (78); the only difference from the entry for mitadv is that the referential argument y of the target predication P need not be an eventuality.

(78) mitfree⟧ = λPλxλyyixi[P(x)(y) ∧ P(xi)(yi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]

Nevertheless, given accomp′, the generalized mitfree still comes along with a conceptual prerequisite: it is only compatible with predications that denote entities that can be extended by the additional participation of others, one prime example being eventualities such as run-of-the-mill activities as discussed in Section 2. The uniform compositional perspective on mitfree then suggests the following hypothesis. Typical positive and comparative adjectives, most K-state verbs, and mode-oriented interpretations of D-state verbs are incompatible with mitfree because they introduce entities that forbid such an accompaniment, whereas superlatives, locatives, a K-state verb such as gehören zu ‘belong to’, and location-oriented interpretations of D-state verbs are compatible with mitfree because they introduce entities that license it. The crucial task now is to motivate this distinction on independent grounds.

4.2.1 Accounting for the constraints on the positive, the comparative, and Kimian state verbs

I will first tackle the adjective-related constraints. To this end, a more detailed look at the semantics of adjectives is necessary. Over the last decade, several researchers have argued that typical adjectives provide both an argument position for the bearer of a certain property and an argument position for the property itself; see Moltmann (2009; 2013); Bücking (2012); Maienborn (2015); McNally & de Swart (2015); Maienborn & Herdtfelder (2017) for discussion. Following Moltmann, I will call these particularized properties tropes. A corresponding entry for groß ‘tall’ is given in (79). Nominalizations such as in (80) render the referential trope argument explicit: they denote the properties themselves instead of their bearers (compare the corresponding well-known ‘externalization’ of silent verbal event arguments by event nominalizations).

(79) ⟦groß⟧ = λxλr.height′(r) ∧ bearer′ (r, x)
(80) height, tiredness, anger

For the present purpose, the crucial ontological trait of tropes is that they are bound to their bearers in a particularly tight way: they are inherent to their respective bearers without providing a spatio-temporal structure that other tropes could live on. That is, Ben’s height is invariably bound to Ben alone and cannot be extended by the accompaniment of some additional bearer; this then provides a plausible reason why free mit is incompatible with both the positive and the comparative. I will spell out the corresponding compositions in turn.14

It is a standard assumption that the positive involves a context-sensitive standard of comparison such that a bearer that complies with this standard ‘stands out’ relative to the property under discussion; see Kennedy (2007) for an elaborate defense of such an approach within a degree-based system. I will use the simplified trope-based variant of it in (81).

(81) ⟦großpos⟧ = λxλr.height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x) ∧ rfpos (height′)

According to (81), a context-sensitive function fpos maps the trope-type for height (that is, the set of possible instances of height, roughly corresponding to measure functions in degree-based systems) onto one of its subtypes, namely, the standard of comparison. For instance, a context could be such that one must be 70 inches tall in order to stand out in height. Correspondingly, the standard of comparison fpos (height′) would be a trope-type R that comprises all possible instances of height (that is, tropes including their bearers) that involve exactly 70 inches. The ordering relation ≥ relates a trope r to either a trope r′ or a trope-type R. If, as is the case here, ≥ relates a trope r to a trope-type R, r must exceed or equal all possible instances of R; in a context as just sketched, this would say that r must be a height that involves at least 70 inches.15 The simple example in (82) then receives the truth conditions in (83); I assume that the state s comes in via the copula or some other trope-closure operation (see Maienborn 2005; 2015; Maienborn & Herdtfelder 2017; the notation ‘s:’ says that s is characterized by the content that follows): (82) is true iff there is a state s such that Ben’s height exceeds or equals all possible instances of the standard of comparison for height as determined by contextual needs.

    1. (82)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. groß.
    2. tall
(83) ⟦Ben ist großpos
  = 1 iff ∃sr[s: height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, Ben) ∧ rfpos(height′)]

Based on the entries in (78) and (81), the combination of the positive with mitfree yields (84), which in turn yields the final result in (86) for the full sentence in (85) (see (66a) above).

(84) ⟦mit großpos⟧ = ⟦mit⟧ (⟦großpos⟧)
  = [λPλxλyyixi[P(x)(y) ∧ P(xi)(yi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxi
yyi]](λxλr.height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x) ∧ rfpos (height′))
  = λxλyyixi[height′(y) ∧ bearer′(y, x) ∧ yfpos (height′) ∧ height′(yi) ∧ bearer′(yi, xi) ∧ yifpos(height′) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]
(85) #Ben ist mit groß.
(86) ⟦Ben ist mit großpos
  = 1 iff ∃syyixi[s: height′(y) ∧ bearer′ (y, Ben) ∧ yfpos(height′) ∧ height′(yi)
∧ bearer′(yi, xi) ∧ yifpos(height′) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ Ben ≰ xiyyi]

In prose: (85) is true iff there is a state such that both Ben’s height and some implicit height of some implicit bearer comply with a standard of comparison for height. Furthermore, the condition accomp′(y, yi) requires that both heights form an integrated whole and that Ben’s hight extends the implicit height. However, given that the implicit height is a trope and thus an inherent property of its bearer lacking a spatio-temporal structure that other tropes could live on, it cannot be extended by another trope. Hence, the result is incoherent, and (85) is predicted to be infelicitous for ontological reasons.

It is noteworthy that the following well-formed examples do not contradict this reasoning.

(87) a. Ben is also tall.
  b. Ben and Mia are (both) tall.
(88) Ben and Mia are (together) 11 feet tall.

The example in (87a) with the additive also presupposes that the height of someone different from Ben complies with the contextual standard. In contrast to mitfree, however, the additive does not enforce any specific relationship between both tropes; hence, there is no conflict with the ontological requirement that tropes are bound to their bearers. (This substantiates one more time why I consider the analysis of free mit in terms of an additive wrong.) The example in (87b) receives a straightforward distributive reading; again, the relevant tropes—Ben’s height and Mia’s height—are independent of each other, which renders their copredication unremarkable. The example in (88) is a bit more tricky. It suggests that tropes are closed under sum formation (that is, the sum of two tropes yields a trope; see also Moltmann 2013: 53–54). However, in contrast to examples based on mitfree, the example in (88) involves a simple collective interpretation. Therefore, it is not about a separate trope that extends another separate trope, but about a complex trope (that is, height of 11 feet) that has a collective entity (that is, Ben and Mia) as its unique bearer. In other words, such collective interpretations do not build on the specific accompaniment between distributed tropes that causes mitfree’s conflict with trope predications.

The explanation for the restriction regarding the comparative is now easy. Following standard assumptions, the comparative differs from the positive by involving a context-independent explicit measure for the comparison. For instance, a trope-based implementation such as (89) for größer als Mia ‘taller than Mia’ says that x’s height must exceed Mia’s height.

(89) ⟦größer als Mia⟧ = λxλr∃r′[height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x) ∧ height′(r′) ∧ bearer′(r′, Mia) ∧ r > r′]

However, as (89) is still a trope predication, this difference does not affect the combinatorics with mitfree; see the composition in (90). Therefore, (91) (see (66b) above) yields the very same ontological mismatch as the positive does. According to the resulting (simplified) representation in (92), Ben’s height would have to extend the implicit height of some implicit bearer, which is impossible (irrespective of the fact that both heights are also said to exceed Mia’s height).

(90) ⟦mit größer als Mia⟧ = ⟦mit⟧ (⟦größer als Mia⟧)
  = [λPλxλyyixi[P(x)(y) ∧ P(xi)(yi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]](λxλrr′[height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x) ∧ height′(r′) ∧ bearer′(r′, Mia) ∧ r > r′])
  = λxλyyixi[∃r′[height′(y) ∧ bearer′(y, x) ∧ height′(r′) ∧ bearer′(r′, Mia) ∧ y > r′] ∧ ∃r′[height′(yi) ∧ bearer′(yi, xi) ∧ height′(r′) ∧ bearer′(r′, Mia) ∧ yi > r′] ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]
(91) #Ben ist mit größer als Mia.
(92) ⟦Ben ist mit größer als Mia⟧
  = 1 iff ∃syyixir′[s: height′(y) ∧ bearer′(y, Ben) ∧ height′(r′) ∧ bearer′(r′, Mia) ∧ y > r′ ∧ height′(yi) ∧ bearer′(yi, xi) ∧ yi > r′ ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ Ben ≰ xi ∧ yyi]

Next, I will turn to the constraints regarding typical K-state verbs (see Section 4.2.2 for a discussion of the constraints regarding D-state verbs). The general idea is that their semantics also involves tropes and thereby predicts that they are infelicitous with mitfree. In fact, Maienborn (2015) has argued that the predications that characterize the K-state in K-state verbs can be conceived of as trope predications. For instance, Ben weighs 70 kg very obviously relates Ben’s particular weight to a measure of weights in general (see Moltmann 2013: 61–69 for more details on tropes and quantities). The sentences Ben loves Mia and Ben resembles Mia identify Ben as a bearer of relational tropes: he exhibits a particularized feeling for Mia or a particularized similarity to her (irrespective of the fact that the specific content of this similarity is left unspecified). For concreteness, I will go through the composition for the example in (93) (see (71a) above).

(93) #Ben ähnelt Tim mit.

Based on the entry in (94) for ähneln, the combination with mitfree yields (95).16 The inclusion of the object, the subject, and the K-state yields the representation in (96) for the full sentence.

(94) ⟦ähneln⟧ = λvλxλr.similarity′(r, v) ∧ bearer′(r, x)
(95) ⟦mit ähneln⟧ = ⟦mit⟧ (⟦ähneln⟧)
  = [λPλvλxλyyixi[P(v)(x)(y) ∧ P(v)(xi)(yi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]] (λvλxλr.similarity′(r, v) ∧ bearer′(r, x))
  = λvλxλyyixi[similarity′(y, v) ∧ bearer′(y, x) ∧ similarity′(yi, v) ∧ bearer′(yi, xi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]
(96) ⟦Ben ähnelt Tim mit⟧
  = 1 iff ∃syyixi[s: similarity′(y, Tim) ∧ bearer′(y, Ben) ∧ similarity′(yi, Tim) ∧ bearer′(yi, xi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ Ben ≰ xiyyi]

As before, the result is ill-formed due to accomp′: Ben’s similarity to Tim cannot extend the similarity to Tim as borne by someone else. This trope-based explanation is further confirmed by the adjective-based counterpart in (97), which is infelicitous in a fully analogous way.

    1. (97)
    1. #Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. Tim
    2. Tim
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. ähnlich.
    2. similar
    1.   ‘Ben belongs to a set of people resembling Tim.’

The given reasoning is based on one noteworthy ingredient. According to the entry in (94), the K-state verb ähneln introduces a trope predication and thus renders the trope argument compositionally accessible to mitadv. That is, the given proposal takes the decomposition of the K-state verb into a trope predication on the one hand and a superordinate K-state predication on the other seriously. In fact, according to (94), the introduction of the K-state including the closure of the trope argument is not rooted in the verb itself, but it is rooted in some silent operation above it. This strengthens the parallel to copula structures with a trope-denoting lexical core (the adjective) and a closure operation introducing the K-state on a higher level (possibly indicated by the explicit copula). Notably, as mentioned in the introduction in Section 1, Zifonun (1996/1997) argues for a base position of the adverbial free mit in the vicinity of the verbal head below direct and indirect objects. Across frameworks, such a position is associated with the compositional access of modifiers to the lexical core of their target entities (see Maienborn & Schäfer 2011 and Bücking 2018 for overviews). This provides initial independent evidence for the given compositional set-up; a full-fledged analysis of the syntax-semantics interface of K-state verbs will be left for another occasion.

In sum, given a uniform compositional approach, the cross-categorial restrictions for mitfree fall under the purview of a uniform conceptual explanation. mitfree is at odds with trope predications, as tropes denote particularized properties that are inherent to their bearers and thus inaccessible to an extension by the accompaniment of an independent other bearer.

I conclude this section with a note of caution. The following examples seem to challenge the given trope-based restriction; arguably, they are felicitous despite the fact that mitfree is combined with a trope-denoting adjective. ((98b) is an abbreviated version of an example I owe to an anonymous reviewer; see https://www.seniorenportal.de/community/forum/haustiere/hasi-ist-krank?tid=126413&page=1#126413, accessed on 09/24/2018.)

    1. (98)
    1. a.
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. schreit
    2. shouts
    1. vor
    2. with
    1. Wut.
    2. anger
    1. Ihr
    2. her
    1. Bruder
    2. brother
    1. Carl
    2. Carl
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. wütend.
    2. angry
    1. ‘Mia is shouting with anger. Her brother Carl belongs to a set of people being angry.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Der
    2. the
    1. süße
    2. sweet
    1. Hase
    2. hare
    1. meiner
    2. of my
    1. Enkelin
    2. grandchild
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. krank.
    2. sick
    1. Unsere
    2. our
    1. ganze
    2. whole
    1. Familie
    2. family
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. krank.
    2. sick
    1. ‘The sweet hare of my grandchild is sick. Our whole family belongs to a set of entities that are sick.’

However, it is well known that type-related restrictions of modifiers can often be sidestepped by adaptive strategies at the semantics-pragmatics interface (see de Swart 2011 for an overview). I hypothesize that examples such as (98) build on adaptations as well. (98a) does not say that Carl is joining the anger that is inherent to Mia; it rather says that Carl is joining the situation that is characterized by Mia acting out her anger. Similarly, (98b) does not say that the family members are joining the disease that is specific to the hare; it says that the family members are joining the unfortunate situation the hare is in by themselves being afflicted with a comparable negative sensation. In both cases, the extended entity is not a trope; it is a bigger situation in which the trope is embedded. This situation provides a spatio-temporal structure that supports an extension by further participants and that is therefore compatible with the contribution of mitfree. The more general prediction is that the acceptability of mitfree covaries with the question of whether adequate superordinate situations can be adapted. Arguably, predications that can be related easily to joint activities or to compassion (such as wütend ‘angry’ and krank ‘sick’ in (98)) are particularly appropriate for such adaptations, whereas an objective atemporal property such as height is not. This reasoning is further supported by the following examples. (I owe (99a) to an anonymous reviewer and (99b) to Frauke Buscher.)

    1. (99)
    1. a.
    1. #Vier
    2.   four
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. gerade.
    2. even
    1.   ‘Four belongs to a set of even numbers.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1.   Bei
    2.   at
    1. dem
    2. the
    1. Auto
    2. car
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Kupplung
    2. clutch
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. kaputt.
    2. broken
    1.   ‘Regarding the car, the clutch belongs to a set of broken things.’

(99a) cannot be adapted at all: atemporal mathematical properties do not suggest superordinate spatio-temporal structures that could be relevant for an accompaniment. By contrast, (99b) is acceptable because the frame-setting modifier bei dem Auto ‘regarding the car’ provides an explicit anchor for a relevant superordinate spatio-temporal structure: the dysfunctionality of the clutch can be related to the more general state the car is in, namely, its having dysfunctional parts. Correspondingly, the dysfunctionality of the clutch and the dysfunctionality of, say, the brake are still independent tropes; their integrity only follows from their being part of the superordinate state the car is in. While I will leave a thorough verification of this line of thought to future research, the following discussion will provide independent evidence for the assumption that the distribution of mitfree depends in crucial ways on the distinction between tropes and states.

4.2.2 Accounting for the well-formed locative predications and the behavior of Davidsonian state verbs

The strategy for an account of the feasible options is obvious: mitfree should target a predication that involves an entity that supports an extension by accompaniment. This can be motivated easily for locative predications such as the locative copula structure in (100) (recall (68a) from above).

    1. (100)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. auf
    2. in
    1. dem
    2. the
    1. Dachboden.
    2. attic
    1. ‘Ben belongs to a set of people in the attic.’

Intuitively, locative predications do not contribute an inherent property of an individual, but an external relation of that individual to some region. The state of being located at a particular region is thus a spatio-temporal structure that other participants can live on; this is the conceptual foundation of why mitfree is possible here. In order to spell out this intuition, the simplest assumption is that the target predications themselves provide locative state predications; see the meaning representation in (101). The combination with mitfree yields (102); (100) then receives the final representation in (103).17

(101) ⟦auf dem Dachboden⟧ = λxλs.s: in′(x, ιa[attic′(a)])
(102) ⟦mit auf dem Dachboden⟧ = ⟦mit⟧(⟦auf dem Dachboden⟧)
  = [λPλxλyyixi[P(x)(y) ∧ P(xi)(yi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]](λxλs.s: in′(x, ιa[attic′(a)]))
  = λxλyyixi[y: in′(x, ιa[attic′(a)]) ∧ yi: in′(xi, ιa[attic′(a)]) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]
(103) ⟦Ben ist mit auf dem Dachboden⟧
  = 1 iff ∃yyixi[y: in′(Ben, ιa[attic′(a)]) ∧ yi: in′(xi, ιa[attic′(a)])
∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ Ben ≰ xiyyi]

The result is well-formed. The state of Ben’s being in the attic is said to accompany the state of someone else’s being in the attic. As motivated above, such an extension of a locative relation is conceptually feasible: being at a particular region is not a trope bound to a unique bearer.

With this explanation in place, it is easy to see why the K-state verb gehören zu ‘belong to’ licenses mitfree; recall (104) (= (71b)).

    1. (104)
    1. Dies
    2. this
    1. gehört
    2. belongs
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. zu
    2. to
    1. unseren
    2. our
    1. Aufgaben.
    2. tasks
    1. ‘This belongs to a set of things that are our tasks.’

The verb gehören zu provides an abstract relation of membership; that is, similarly to locatives and in sharp contrast to the K-state verbs discussed in Section 4.2.1, it does not contribute an inherent property of an entity, but an external relation of that entity to some group. As the state of belonging to some group licenses an extension, no conflict with the accompaniment introduced by mitfree arises.18

The behavior of locative D-state verbs can be traced back to the patterns already established. The corresponding reasoning is based on the intuition that locative D-state verbs contribute a bipartite meaning structure: the subject referent is attributed both a locative state and a posture (see again Kaufmann 1995: 98–120 for a more general discussion). Furthermore, the posture relates to particular parts of the subject referent and their organization (for instance, according to Kaufmann’s work, standing involves a vertical orientation of the subject’s prominent axis). It is thus plausible that the posture amounts to a particularized property, that is, a trope. In well-formed examples such as (105a) (= (72a)), mitfree scopes above the integration of the locative. In fact, Zifonun (1996/1997) shows that the reversed linearization is ungrammatical; see (105b).

    1. (105)
    1. a.
    1.   Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. an
    2. at
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Ecke.
    2. corner
    1.   ‘Ben belongs to a set of people standing at the corner.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. *Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. an
    2. at
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Ecke
    2. corner
    1. mit.
    2. mitfree

I conjecture that mitfree here combines with a predication that makes the locative component compositionally available, while the trope component is already closed; see the sketch in (106) and the result of its composition with mitfree in (107).

(106) ⟦an der Ecke stehen⟧ = λxλsr[[s: at′(x, ιc[corner′(c)])] ∧ stand′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x)]
(107) ⟦mit an der Ecke stehen⟧ = ⟦mit⟧ (⟦an der Ecke stehen⟧)
  = [λPλxλyyixi[P(x)(y) ∧ P(xi)(yi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]] (λxλsr[[s: at′(x, ιc[corner′(c)])] ∧ stand′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x)])
  = λxλyyixi[∃r[[y: at′(x, ιc[corner′(c)])] ∧ stand′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x)]
∧ ∃r[[yi: at′(xi, ιc[corner′(c)])] ∧ stand′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, xi)]
∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]

Irrespective of how the composition proceeds (see below for a few remarks), (107) predicts (105a) to be well-formed. The state of x’s being at the corner is said to accompany the state of someone else’s being at the corner, which is fully analogous to the simple copula structure in (103) above. It does not matter that x and its implicit alternative xi must also be bearers of posture tropes. According to (107), these tropes do not interact and thus do not cause a conceptual mismatch.

The situation is different for mode-oriented readings; recall the ill-formed example in (108) (= (74)).

    1. (108)
    1. #Das
    2.   the
    1. Kalb
    2. calf
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. schon,
    2. already
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Mutterkuh
    2. mother cow
    1. steht
    2. stands
    1. mit.
    2. mitfree
    1.   ‘The calf is already standing, and the mother cow belongs to a set of entities standing.’

As this reading demotes the locative component, it is plausible that it makes the posture component compositionally available; manner modification as in (109) corroborates this claim. Correspondingly, mitfree would target a trope predication as sketched in (110), which yields the result in (111).

(109) Das Kalb steht unsicher.
(110) ⟦stehen⟧ = λxλr[stand′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x)]
(111) ⟦mit stehen⟧ = ⟦mit⟧(⟦stehen⟧)
  = [λPλxλyyixi[P(x)(y) ∧ P(xi)(yi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]](λxλr[stand′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x)])
  = λxλyyixi[stand′(y) ∧ bearer′(y, x) ∧ stand′(yi) ∧ bearer′(yi, xi)
∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]

As desired, (111) predicts that (108) is infelicitous. Due to accomp′(y, yi), the particularized posture y inherent to x would have to extend the posture yi inherent to some other entity, which is conceptually impossible.

In a nutshell, the idea then is that locative D-state verbs provide two compositional anchors. The first anchor is a trope predication that is incompatible with mitfree; the second anchor is a state predication that is available above a locative PP argument and that is compatible with mitfree. This set-up begs the follow-up question of where the D-state is integrated. Given that locative D-state verbs and locative copula structures differ for instance with regard to perception reports (see Section 4.1 and Maienborn 2003; 2005 for details), the referential argument of the full verbal projection cannot be the locative K-state argument s in (107) as such. One option would be that the locative state predication and the trope predication are integrated within a higher-order D-state predication. This would mirror the situation with K-state verbs as discussed in Section 4.2.1, where I have also suggested that there is an independent higher-order closure operation. The difference would be that the closure introduces a D-state with D-state verbs and a K-state with K-state verbs. I would like to leave a more detailed discussion of these compositional challenges to future work. The solution should not affect the principled idea that I have put forward here in order to explain the distribution of mitfree within the projection of locative D-state verbs.

I will conclude this subsection with a brief comment on D-state verbs that introduce a specific mode of sensory perception and on the D-state verb schlafen ‘sleep’; recall the ill-formed examples in (112) (= (76a)) and (113) (= (75b)).

    1. (112)
    1. #Der
    2.   the
    1. Teller
    2. plate
    1. glänzte,
    2. gleamed
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Tasse
    2. cup
    1. glänzte
    2. gleamed
    1. mit.
    2. mitfree
    1.   ‘The plate was gleaming, and the cup belonged to a set of entities gleaming.’
    1. (113)
    1. #Das
    2.   the
    1. Kind
    2. child
    1. schläft,
    2. sleeps
    1. und
    2. and
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Katze
    2. cat
    1. schläft
    2. sleeps
    1. mit.
    2. mitfree
    1.   ‘The child is sleeping, and the cat belongs to a set of entities sleeping.’

It is intuitively plausible that the internal structure of these verbs does not introduce an abstract relation of membership, but a trope. More specifically, glänzen introduces a luster, that is, a particularized visual appearance rooted in the surface structure of its bearer. Correspondingly, the cup’s luster cannot extend the luster of the plate, which explains why (112) is odd. Similarly, dormancy as such (that is, the property disposed of its spatio-temporal coordinates; recall the contrast to (75a) above) is inherent to its bearer and thus inaccessible to an extension by someone else’s dormancy.19

4.2.3 Accounting for the well-formed superlative predications

Finally, I will turn to the intriguing observation that the superlative is generally well-formed with mitfree despite the fact that corresponding positives and comparatives are not. I argue that this contrast has the following principled explanation. The superlative contributes a type of meaning that is very different from the meaning of the positive and the comparative, namely, it partitions a context-set according to some measure. Therefore, mitfree escapes the interaction with underlying trope predications and instead interacts with this partition in a predictable way. I will provide independent reasons for this perspective on the superlative and then spell out a corresponding composition with mitfree.

The first observation relates to the lacking entailment in (114) (= (8a)).

    1. (114)
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest
    1.  
    1. Ben
    2. Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. der
    2. the
    1. größte.
    2. tallest

For Zifonun (1996/1997) and Bücker (2012), this behavior is idiosyncratic and thus a key argument for the treatment of free mit plus superlative as a separate construction: mit would eliminate the uniqueness condition of the superlative; moreover, the adverbial counterpart supports the corresponding entailment, which would speak against a uniform treatment in a principled way. However, this reasoning does not take into account that this entailment pattern is fully regular for the superlative in distributive contexts; see the simple plural superlative in (115). Notably, (115) still involves uniqueness. The difference from a standard singular predication is merely that the predication does not relate to a unique individual, but to a unique set of individuals, which in this case consists of Ben and Paul.

(115) Ben and Paul are the tallest. ↛ {Ben / Paul} is the tallest.

It is thus highly plausible that the entailment patterns in (114) and (115) have a common source. Both predications involve unique sets of individuals that comply with a certain height; as sets of individuals are involved, it is impossible for both cases to deduce which particular individual is the tallest. The difference between them is the following. The standard plural in (115) exhaustifies the individuals in the relevant set by explicit reference to them; mitfree in (114), by contrast, merely indicates that there must be others in the relevant set without, however, specifying their number and identity. Furthermore, the distribution obtained by mitfree does not yield an ordinary plural predication; it is still a modifier to the given singular predication, which is why (114) and (115) are morphologically distinct. In other words, mitfree does exactly the same in the combination with the superlative as it does in its other uses. It is a modifier that marks the existence of implicit co-participants and thereby triggers plurality effects.

Given the analogy between mitfree and the plural, a closer look at plural superlatives in general is necessary. The research on plural superlatives has identified two crucial challenges to their proper analysis: the distributivity problem and the cutoff problem; see Stateva (2005); Herdan (2008); Fitzgibbons et al. (2008). The distributivity problem is a direct consequence of the lacking entailment in (115). It says that the combination of a standard degree-based semantics for the superlative, as in (116) (see Heim 1999; Coppock & Beaver 2014), with a standard distributional operator for plural predication, as in (117) (see Lasersohn 1998; 2011), yields a contradictory and, thus, wrong result, as in (118). (I assume that G is some appropriate functor from sets of singular individuals to plural individuals.)

(116) ⟦the tallest⟧ = λxd[tall′(x, d) ∧ ∀x′[[C(x′) ∧ x′ ≰ x] → ¬tall′(x′, d)]]
  ‘set of x such that x is d-tall and nobody that is in the context-set C, but distinct from x, is d-tall’
(117) λPλxy[yxP(y)]
(118) ⟦Ben and Paul are the tallest⟧
  = 1 iff ∀y[yG({Ben, Paul}) → ∃d[tall′(y, d) ∧ ∀x′[[C(x′) ∧ x′ ≰ y] → ¬tall′(x′, d)]]]

In prose: A sentence such as Ben and Paul are the tallest would be true iff Ben is taller than everyone else in the context-set, and Paul is taller than everyone else in the context-set. This is clearly impossible, as Ben would have to be taller than Paul, while Paul would have to be taller than Ben. Intuitively, there is an obvious way out. The superlative should induce a partition of the context-set such that Ben and Paul are taller than all others in the context-set, irrespective of how their heights are ranked to each other. This already suggests an analysis of the superlative that is not about the assignment of particularized properties, but about the bipartite partition of a context-set into the set of those individuals that comply with a certain height and those that do not.

This reasoning becomes even more evident with regard to the second challenge, the so-called cutoff problem. This problem can be illustrated by the dialogue in (119), adapted from Fitzgibbons et al. (2008: (6)).

(119) A: Ben and Paul are the tallest students.
  B: You are forgetting Eric; he is only an inch shorter than Ben.
  A: My mistake. Ben, Paul, and Eric are the tallest students.

Despite the fact that Ben and Paul could be the tallest students in the given scenario, A can accept a correction of his corresponding statement and include Eric in the set of the tallest students. This makes sense only on the assumption that the superlative semantics involves a context-sensitive cutoff that divides the context-set into the unique group that complies with this cutoff and the remaining individuals that do not comply with it. The given scenario could be such that a difference of just one inch should not matter for the partition, for instance, because all others in the context-set are significantly shorter than Eric. Fitzgibbons et al. (2008: 303) conclude that “the context supplies a natural cutoff point on the relevant scale which determines, for a given gradable predicate R, a unique group of R-est individuals”. In other words, the superlative contributes a cutoff that must be such that it is satisfied by exactly those individuals the superlative predicates of. Crucially, superlative constructions differ in the degree to which this unique group of individuals is made explicit. Standard direct predications exhaustify the members of the unique group of R-est individuals within their minimal predication domain. Therefore, A identifies different sets in his two statements in (119). This is also the reason why (120) with two separate minimal predications is infelicitous (irrespective of Ben’s and Paul’s actual heights). The first conjunct identifies Ben as the only member of the set, while the second conjunct identifies Paul as its single member.20

(120) #Ben is the tallest, and Paul is the tallest.

Other uses of the superlative do not make the relevant set explicit. This is typical for the superlative in referential position (see Herdan 2008 for a general discussion). For instance, (121) does not identify the relevant family members directly; however, contextual needs guide the partition. If there are three rows, the cutoff should be such that roughly one-third of the people in the context-set belong to the unique group of the tallest family members. A speaker can also be precise about the cardinality of the relevant group and thereby guide the determination of the cutoff that is relevant for the partition; see (122), which could be used in a scenario with six apples that are all small, but distinguishable in size.

(121) [At the photographer] The tallest family members should stand in the back row.
(122) I would like to have the five biggest apples from that basket!

It now nearly goes without saying that mitfree plus superlative involves facets of both direct predications and referential uses. While it is made explicit that the subject argument belongs to the unique set of R-est individuals, the alternatives are not made explicit, which is why the relevant unique set is not clearly identified. Crucially, however, this is exactly as expected, given the usual semantics of mitfree in terms of implicit co-participants.

Based on this overview, I propose the meaning representation in (123) for the superlative; (124) defines the crucial context-sensitive function fsup. The proposal resorts to tropes instead of degrees because this makes it consistent with the above analyses of the positive and the comparative.21

(123) ⟦der größte⟧ = λxλsr[s: height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x) ∧ rfsup(height′)]
(124) fsup is a context-sensitive function that maps a trope-type to one of its subtypes such that, given a context-set C, all individuals in Cpred (that is, all individuals that are predicated of in the superlative’s minimal predication domain) comply with this subtype, and no individual in the complementary set Ccontrast complies with this subtype.

This proposal direcly implements the idea that the superlative effectuates the partition of a context-set according to some appropriate cutoff, namely, an appropriate subtype of the trope type under discussion. It comes along with two crucial traits. For one, it is compatible with run-of-the-mill distribution; for instance, a standard direct plural predication receives the truth conditions in (125): Ben’s height must exceed or equal the cutoff fsup(height′), and Paul’s height must exceed or equal this cutoff.

(125) ⟦Ben and Paul are the tallest⟧
  = 1 iff ∀y[yG({Ben, Paul}) → ∃sr[s: height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, y)
rfsup(height′)]]

This simple distribution is feasible because the value of the relevant cutoff is independent of the distribution, but dependent on the minimal predication domain as a whole. Therefore, the cutoff must be such that Ben’s height and Paul’s height comply with it (Ben and Paul are in Cpred), whereas the heights of all others do not comply with it (all others are in Ccontrast).

The second crucial trait is that the superlative does not contribute a trope predication, but a state predication with the relevant trope arguments being closed and thus having narrow scope. This is conceptually sound: the superlative does not assign a certain particularized property; instead, it affects the question of whether an existing particularized property licenses the membership of its bearer to the unique group of individuals that comply with a certain cutoff.

Both traits facilitate a straightforward combination of the semantics of the superlative with the semantics of mitfree; see (126). (127) provides the corresponding final representation for the initial example.

(126) ⟦mit der größte⟧ = ⟦mit⟧(⟦der größte⟧)
  = [λPλxλyyixi[P(x)(y) ∧ P(xi)(yi) ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]](λxλsr[s: height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x) ∧ rfsup(height′)])
  = λxλyyixi[∃r[y: height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, x) ∧ rfsup (height′)] ∧ ∃r[yi: height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, xi) ∧ rfsup(height′)] ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ xxiyyi]
(127) ⟦Ben ist mit der größte⟧
  = 1 iff ∃yyixi
[∃r[y: height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, Ben) ∧ rfsup(height′)] ∧ ∃r[yi: height′(r) ∧ bearer′(r, xi) ∧ rfsup(height′)] ∧ accomp′(y, yi) ∧ Ben ≰ xiyyi]

In prose: (127) is true iff the state of Ben bearing a height that exceeds or equals a context-sensitive cutoff for heights accompanies the state of someone else’s bearing a height that exceeds or equals this cutoff. This is as desired. The accompaniment does not relate tropes, but states of being bearers of certain tropes, which is ontologically well-formed. Furthermore, given that the minimal predication domain involves both the explicit individual in subject position and the implicit individuals as introduced by the modifying mitfree, the cutoff must be such that Ben’s height and at least someone else’s height comply with it (Ben and the implicit bearers are in Cpred), whereas all others do not comply with it (all others are in Ccontrast). As expected, there is thus only partial explicit knowledge of who belongs to the unique set of the tallest individuals in the context. Therefore, and similarly to the situation with referential plural superlatives, contextual needs control the specification of the cutoff: it must be such that a reasonable partition of the context-set emerges.

Finally, I would like to mention one further welcome prediction. For the given analysis of mitfree plus superlative, it is crucial that mitfree interacts with a level of representation that is about the context-sensitive partition of individuals. However, there are also uses of the superlative that are not about this partition, but about the assignment of high-ranking particularized properties. This ‘elative’ interpretation comes along with the absence of the definite determiner, as in (128a). As expected, mitfree is incompatible with this interpretation of the superlative, as shown by (128b).

    1. (128)
    1. a.
    1.   Peter
    2.   Peter
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. größte
    2. biggest
    1. Mühe
    2. trouble
    1. damit,
    2. with it
    1. dieses
    2. this
    1. Problem
    2. problem
    1. zu
    2. to
    1. lösen.
    2. solve
    1.   ‘Peter is having a very hard time solving this problem.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. #Peter
    2.   Peter
    1. hat
    2. has
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. größte
    2. biggest
    1. Mühe
    2. trouble
    1. damit,
    2. with it
    1. dieses
    2. this
    1. Problem
    2. problem
    1. zu
    2. to
    1. lösen.
    2. solve

5 Conclusion

This paper has been concerned with the semantics and pragmatics of mit ‘with’ as a free particle in German. I have proposed that mitfree contributes a modifier with the following uniform interpretation. It distributes its target predication over the explicit subject and implicit alternatives in such a way that the subject is said to accompany an implicit situation by participating in a corresponding situation. The proposal covers the use of mitfree within both eventive and stative predications, including its striking combination with the superlative form of adjectives. I have argued that this compositional approach considerably improves on previous analyses that consider mitfree in its adverbial use to be an additive focus particle or a retrievable prepositional phrase, and that are forced to posit a separate construction for its use with the superlative.

More specifically, the proposal is motivated by the following key pieces of evidence. First, mitfree introduces a distinction between explicit discourse-transparent content and implicit discourse-opaque content. The accompaniment of a host situation by the subject is identified as the explicit content and is thus accessible to cross-sentential anaphors, operators, and questions. The host situation including its alternative participants is identified as the implicit content and is thus inaccessible to discourse-related operations. Notably, mitfree is not sensitive to focus and does not introduce presupposed or projective content.

Second, the accompaniment is characterized by three traits in particular: it forms an integrated whole with the host situation, it extends its host situation, and finally, the subject receives a regular participant role in the situation under discussion. These traits make the right predictions concerning various details of interpretation. For instance, the subject is a regular co-agent or co-bearer within the joint situation, while it nonetheless plays a concomitant role in it. Furthermore, integrity conditions sensitive to situation types determine in principled ways whether conjoined situations share participants and whether mitfree is veridical (see below for the superlative).

Third, the accompaniment-based analysis provides a principled explanation for a wide range of distributional contrasts that are unaccounted for in previous work: mitfree is compatible with predication types that introduce entities that can be extended by the accompaniment of further participants; this applies to eventive and stative predications such as activity predications, locative predications including location-oriented interpretations of position verbs, and the predication that is introduced by the superlative form of adjectives. By contrast, mitfree is incompatible with predication types that are conceptually at odds with a corresponding accompaniment; this applies to predications that denote tropes, that is, particularized properties inherent to their bearers. This group comprises predications that are introduced by the positive and the comparative form of typical adjectives, predications that are introduced by the internal core of typical so-called Kimian state verbs, and predications that underlie mode-oriented interpretations of other kinds of state verbs. Crucially, the decision of whether a certain predication licenses or prohibits an extension by accompaniment is justified by independent grammatical and conceptual considerations. In particular, the cross-categorial restrictions fall under the purview of a uniform conceptual explanation that makes crucial use of the notion of tropes; this corroborates the assumption that tropes should be considered an essential part of natural language ontology. I have also detailed why the superlative provides a higher-order semantics that yields a partition of a context-set according to a certain cutoff and therefore escapes trope-related restrictions. Furthermore, given the uniform distributive semantics of mitfree, the seemingly irregular fact that mitfree with the superlative is not veridical could be traced back to a regular general trait of the superlative in distributive contexts.

At first sight, mitfree in German appears to be a rather peculiar lexical item. However, the present paper shows how fruitful an approach to it in terms of regular composition can be. This approach has disclosed regularities of mitfree not recognized before. Crucially, it has also advanced our understanding of more general topics such as the internal semantic structure of stative predications, the role of accompanying relations within natural language ontology, and the question of how to model the interpretation of the superlative given its behavior in distributive contexts. I conclude by pointing out one of the remaining challenges.22 There are types of predications the combinatorics of which with mitfree has not yet been discussed. For instance, mitfree seems to be generally incompatible with simple noun-based predications, as in (129).

    1. (129)
    1. #Ben
    2.   Ben
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. {Linguist
    2. {linguist
    1. /
    2. /
    1. ein
    2. an
    1. Idiot
    2. idiot
    1. /
    2. /
    1. ein
    2. a
    1. Berliner
    2. Berlin
    1. Bäcker}.
    2. baker}
    1.   ‘Ben belongs to a set of people who are {linguists / idiots / bakers in Berlin}.’

The results of the present paper suggest that these nominal predications contribute particularized properties that cannot be shared. While I consider this hypothesis reasonable, its consequences should be spelled out in more detail in future work. In addition to such further constraints, there are also further feasible options. For instance, several predications for causal relations support mitfree, as shown in (130); see also Zifonun et al. (1997: 2146) and Hoekstra (2004: 123/(13)).

    1. (130)
    1. a.
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. verantwortlich
    2. responsible
    1. für
    2. for
    1. den
    2. the
    1. Vortrag.
    2. talk
    1. ‘Mia belongs to a set of people that are responsible for the talk.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Mia
    2. Mia
    1. ist
    2. is
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. in
    2. in
    1. der
    2. the
    1. Verantwortung
    2. responsibility
    1. für
    2. for
    1. den
    2. the
    1. Vortrag.
    2. talk
    1. ‘Mia belongs to a set of people that bear responsibility for the talk.’
    1.  
    1. c.
    1. Dies
    2. this
    1. sei
    2. be
    1. mit
    2. mitfree
    1. {ein
    2. {an
    1. Anlass
    2. occasion
    1. /
    2. /
    1. ein
    2. a
    1. Grund}
    2. reason}
    1. für
    2. for
    1. weitere
    2. further
    1. Debatten.
    2. debates
    1. ‘Let this belong to a set of things that {prompt / cause} further debates.’

Notably, these options are independent of syntactic categories. This is in line with the assumption that the distribution of mitfree depends on conceptual conditions; these conditions can typically be associated with certain categories, but they are not necessarily bound to them. What could a conceptual explanation look like? A plausible hypothesis would be that these causal predications do not introduce particularized properties, but abstract relations for causes that, similarly to locative relations, license the accompaniment by secondary participants. I will leave it to future work whether this hypothesis can withstand closer scrutiny. In any case, the compositional approach forces one to consider such principled explanations for constraints and options instead of merely stating that they exist.

Abbreviations

accomp′ = accompaniment relation as defined in (54), ag′ = agent relation, AP = adjectival phrase, bearer′ = bearer relation, C = context-set, Ccontrast = individuals of a context-set that are not in a minimal predication domain, comitative′ = comitative relation, Cpred = individuals of a context-set that are in a minimal predication domain, DP = determiner phrase, D-state = Davidsonian state, fpos = context-sensitive function relevant for the meaning of the positive form, fsup = context-sensitive function relevant for the meaning of the superlative form, G = function from sets of singular individuals to plural individuals, i as a subscript = implicit, K-state = Kimian state, mitadv = adverbial free mit, mitfree = generalized free mit, mitsup = free mit with the superlative, pos as a subscript = positive form, PP = prepositional phrase, PTC = particle, REFL = reflexive, th′ = theme relation, ≤ = is part of, ≰ = is not part of

Notes

  1. English does not have an equivalent expression. For ease of presentation, I will generally use the verb ‘belong to’ for the translation of free mit. However, this translation is simplified compared to the particular analysis of free mit that I will develop in this paper. [^]
  2. Notably, this analysis does not imply that mitadv is a regular prepositional phrase. In fact, Zifonun considers mitadv a syntactically defective phrase. For the purposes of this paper, I am agnostic to these details and instead focus on questions of interpretation. [^]
  3. Although I will not tackle them here, mitadv still raises intricate morpho-syntactic questions. For instance, according to Zifonun (1996/1997: 220), mitadv cannot be fronted on its own, which calls for a principled explanation. An anonymous reviewer notes that the syntactic behavior of mitadv could be related to the controversy of whether particles should be treated as syntactic heads or as maximal projections; see, for instance, Bayer (1996), Büring & Hartmann (2001), Sudhoff (2010), and Bayer & Trotzke (2015) for discussion. [^]
  4. The accent on Seifenkiste ‘soapbox’ induces that alternatives to soapboxes are pragmatically relevant as well. However, this effect does not interact with the contribution by mitadv. [^]
  5. The stacked interpretation is obvious for situations involving an established set of travelers: it is asserted that Ben is joining this set, while it is presupposed that someone else is joining the set as well. However, (22) can also be used in a situation lacking an established set. In this case, the identification of alternatives—independently of whether they are required by mitadv or auch—can proceed in circles and thereby blur the stacked interpretation. (22) is then even compatible with a situation with only two travelers. The assertion in (23a) would involve a set consisting of, for instance, only Mia, while the presupposition in (23b) would involve a set consisting of only Ben. That is, ‘a set of people riding to Rome’ is identified differently in the assertion and in the presupposition. As the context does not specify a particular set, this complementary identification of alternatives is a regular option. [^]
  6. An anonymous reviewer notes that this last evidence is only conclusive if the interaction between nur ‘only’ and auch ‘also’ is different. To my intuition, (i) is in fact worse than (24) (given that both nur and auch relate to alternatives of the subject).
      1. (i)
      1. ??Nur
      2.     only
      1. Ben
      2. Ben
      1. ist
      2. is
      1. auch
      2. also
      1. nach
      2. to
      1. Rom
      2. Rome
      1. gefahren.
      2. ridden
      1.     ‘Only Ben is also riding to Rome.’
    In order to sidestep a conflict between the focus-related exclusion and inclusion of alternatives, nur would have to relate to the presupposition made by the additive: Ben would be said to be the only one riding to Rome in addition to someone presupposed. This mixture of meaning dimensions could account for the given intuition; I thank Stefan Sudhoff for this suggestion. However, the anonymous reviewer considers (i) inconspicuous. [^]
  7. Zifonun (1996/1997) also suggests that mitadv should not be conflated with true elliptical cases such as (32b). However, she does not seem to notice that reconstruction accounts (including her own) are at odds with the fact that mitadv is limited to a comitative use. [^]
  8. Notably, if the object instead of the subject were focused in (36b) (correlating with deaccenting auch), the clause would be felicitous. In this case, Strong Contextual Felicity would be satisfiable via the context information that Ben is known as a tinkerer; plausible alternative objects would be bikes or cars. [^]
  9. The focus particles auch ‘also’ and nur ‘only’ do not license such content-related contrasts. The finding thus provides further evidence against a focus particle treatment of mitadv. [^]
  10. Correspondingly, I will also remain agnostic as to the question of how the implicit arguments introduced by mitadv relate to the distinction between at-issue content and not at-issue content as discussed in, for instance, Potts (2005); Amaral et al. (2007); Jayez (2010); Simons et al. (2010); Tonhauser (2012). [^]
  11. Predicates denoting self-propelled motions provide independent evidence for the assumption that mitadv singles out the activity component of verbal predicates. These predicates support both an atelic activity interpretation and a telic accomplishment interpretation. However, mitadv renders the telic interpretation grammatically inaccessible, as shown in (i). The compositionally active variable for the explicit eventuality licenses an activity-sensitive for-adverbial, but not an accomplishment-sensitive in-adverbial.
      1. (i)
      1. Ben
      2. Ben
      1. ist
      2. is
      1. {2
      2. {2
      1. Minuten
      2. minutes
      1. lang / #in
      2. long / in
      1. 2
      2. 2
      1. Minuten}
      2. minutes}
      1. mit
      2. mitadv
      1. zur
      2. to the
      1. Hütte
      2. cottage
      1. gelaufen.
      2. walked
      1. ‘For 2 minutes Ben belonged to a set of people walking to the cottage.’ /
      2. ‘In 2 minutes Ben belonged to a set of people walking to the cottage.’
    One might be puzzled by the additional observation that these predicates still support veridicality. This, however, can be easily explained by the fact that the causal effect of self-propelled motions do not depend on the joint forces of all participants. [^]
  12. For reasons of space, I will not be able to discuss the full range of relevant environments. In particular, I will confine the discussion to predicative uses of mitsup. Furthermore, I will not discuss noun-based direct predications such as be a baker or be a reason for; see the conclusion in Section 5 for a few remarks. [^]
  13. I thank Johanna Herdtfelder for drawing my attention to duften. See footnote 19 for qualifications regarding schlafen and glänzen. [^]
  14. The example in (i) shows that particularized properties are not referentially identical to each other. This affirms the assumption that tropes are particulars inherent to their bearers.
    (i) #Ben’s height is Mia’s height.
    This conclusion is not contradicted by the fact that tropes can be equivalent, as in (ii).
    (ii) Ben’s height is the same as Mia’s height.
    Roughly, the equivalence builds on the identity of the degrees that are associated with Ben’s and Mia’s height, but not on the identity of the properties themselves; see Moltmann (2015) for analogous examples and further discussion. [^]
  15. See Moltmann (2009) for a formally elaborate trope-based system of comparative concepts; the given simplified implementation suffices for the present purpose. It is also not crucial to spell out the way the context-sensitive function fpos works; see Kennedy (2007) for details. [^]
  16. Technically, the composition builds on the assumption that mitfree is not restricted to two-place predicates, but that it can pass on additional argument slots; only this assumption renders mitfree compatible with a three-place function such as ähneln. Such a polymorphism is typical of modifiers and thus a natural extension of the entry in (78). [^]
  17. The details of the relevant closure operation are not spelled out here. In contrast to the trope-based copula structures, the PP already provides an appropriate K-state here; this licenses the identification of the lexically given K-state with the one that is existentially closed. The particular implementation of this identification is not important for my main argument; notably, the fact that both APs and locative PPs can provide the lexical core of copula structures is independent of the distribution of mitfree. [^]
  18. There is thus a clear distinction between ‘to belong to entities that bear a certain property’ and ‘to bear a certain property’. Notably, my simplified English paraphrases generally build on the former predication. Therefore, these paraphrases are not fully accurate and not sensitive to the specific constraints of the original clauses in German. An anonymous reviewer notes that the combination of mitfree with groß ‘tall’ gets considerably better in partitive constructions; see his example in (i).
      1. (i)
      1. Peter
      2. Peter
      1. ist
      2. is
      1. mit
      2. mitfree
      1. einer
      2. one
      1. der
      2. of the
      1. großen
      2. tall
      1. in
      2. in
      1. der
      2. the
      1. Mannschaft.
      2. team
      1. ‘Peter belongs to a set of tall people in the team.’
    Arguably, partitive constructions introduce a superordinate relation of membership; that is, they convey ‘to belong to entities that bear a certain property’ instead of ‘to bear a certain property’. This correctly predicts that mitadv is better in (i) than in standard direct predications. Notably, the partition of entities into groups will also play a crucial role for the analysis of mitadv with the superlative. [^]
  19. Recall from Section 4.2.1 that certain trope-related restrictions can be sidestepped by the adaptation of appropriate superordinate spatio-temporal structures that support extensions. This is true for (112) and (113) as well. Let there be a situation where the dinnerware is gleaming as a whole; correspondingly, the gleaming of the cup can be conceived of as living on this superordinate temporal situation. Under this perspective, (112) is conceptually possible and thus receives a better grammaticality judgment. As for sleeping, examples such as the following are revealing. (I owe it to an anonymous reviewer.)
      1. (i)
      1. Newspaper article on anesthesia, see https://www.wlz-online.de/magazin/digital/angst-schlaeft-5455316.html, accessed on 10/08/2018
      1. Die
      2. the
      1. Angst
      2. fear
      1. schläft
      2. sleeps
      1. mit.
      2. mitfree
      1. ‘The fear belongs to a set of entities sleeping.’
    (i) is acceptable. However, it does not convey that the dormancy inherent to the fear accompanies the dormancy inherent to some independent other entity. The fear rather belongs to a superordinate sleeping individual. Therefore, the dormancy of the fear can be easily conceived of as living on the dormancy of this superordinate individual. In other words, it remains within the limits of a higher-order inherent property; in fact, (i) specifies one aspect of what it means for individuals to sleep while under anesthetic. Finally, it is noteworthy that this use involves an adapted interpretation of the verb itself (usually, sleep selects individuals as wholes instead of their properties). [^]
  20. Fitzgibbons et al. (2008: 316–317) discuss an example that is analogous to (120). They also speculate on the role of minimal clauses for its account, but abandon this idea. In footnote 21, I briefly explain why I retain it instead of adopting the proposal that is finally preferred by Fitzgibbons et al. (2008). [^]
  21. While the proposal is an original one, it builds heavily on aspects of previous analyses; see Fitzgibbons et al. (2008) for an overview. The partitioning of the context-set is inspired by the shrinking of the context-set C in Stateva’s (2005) original proposal, the role of cutoffs and of minimal predication domains is inspired by Herdan (2008) and Fitzgibbons et al. (2008), and the use of a context-sensitive function is inspired by the use of a context-sensitive function for the positive as in Kennedy (2007). For reasons of space, I cannot evaluate the various analyses of the (plural) superlative. However, I will briefly explain why I cannot use the analysis that is ultimately defended by Fitzgibbons et al. (2008). They propose a logical form that relies on the so-called ‘double star’ (‘**’) distributivity operator in the scope of the superlative morpheme, as in (i). (This operator is usually used for transitive relations with plural arguments such as Ben and Paul love Mia and Pia.)
    (i) Fitzgibbons et al. (2008: (21))
      [Ben and Paul [-est [**tall]]]
    I see two problems for a transfer of this proposal to mitfree plus superlative. First, the distributive effect of mitfree plus superlative hinges on mitfree itself. However, mitfree has a higher syntactic position than the superlative. In fact, mitfree cannot project in a position that is closer to the adjective; see (ii). A surface-oriented syntax thus predicts that the distribution scopes above the contribution of the superlative structure, contrary to (i).
      1. (ii)
      1. *Ben
      2.   Ben
      1. ist
      2. is
      1. der
      2. the
      1. mit
      2. mitfree
      1. größte.
      2. tallest
    Second, it is also semantically impossible that mitfree has scope below the superlative. The narrow scope would enforce a combination of mitfree with the meaning of the positive. However, as argued at length above, this option is ruled out on independent grounds. Against this background, the behavior of mitfree plus superlative could even be used as a vital argument against the **-analysis of distributive superlatives in general. A thorough discussion will be left to future research. [^]
  22. One would also like to better understand the relation between mitfree and its use as a bound particle; recall the examples (11) and (12) from the introduction. While the meaning of the bound particle is certainly close to the meaning proposed for mitfree, it is an open question whether there are fine-grained differences. [^]

Acknowledgements

This research was supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (project A1 of the SFB 833 “The Construction of Meaning”). I very much thank three anonymous reviewers, Claudia Maienborn, and Sarah Metzger for their detailed and very helpful comments on earlier versions of the present paper. I owe thanks to Frauke Buscher, Johanna Herdtfelder, Julia Lukassek, Edith Scheifele, Stefan Sudhoff, and Sarah Zobel for the extensive discussion of various details. Finally, parts of this work were presented at “Event Semantics 16” in Düsseldorf (November 25, 2016), at the Leibniz-Zentrum Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft in Berlin (July 04, 2017), and at “Linguistischer Arbeitskreis Köln” in Cologne (January 10, 2018). Thanks to the audiences for their valuable feedback.

Competing Interests

The author has no competing interests to declare.

References

Amaral, Patricia Matos, Craige Roberts & E. Allyn Smith. 2007. Review of Potts 2005. Linguistics and Philosophy 30. 707–749. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-008-9025-2

Bayer, Josef. 1996. Directionality and logical form: On the scope of focusing particles and Wh-in-situ. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Bayer, Josef & Andreas Trotzke. 2015. The derivation and interpretation of left peripheral discourse particles. In Josef Bayer, Roland Hinterhölzl & Andreas Trotzke (eds.), Discourse-oriented syntax, 13–40. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/la.226

Bücker, Jörg. 2012. Mit die schönsten und heitersten Stunden: System und Gebrauch der Partikelvorkommen von mit im gesprochenen Deutsch. Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft 31. 207–233. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/zfs-2012-0008

Bücking, Sebastian. 2012. Müdigkeit und Müde-Sein: Zur Semantik adjektivbasierter Zustandsnominalisierungen im Deutschen. Linguistische Berichte 232. 361–397.

Bücking, Sebastian. 2018. The compositional semantics of modification. In Mark Aronoff (ed.), Oxford research encyclopedia of linguistics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780199384655.013.354

Büring, Daniel & Katharina Hartmann. 2001. The syntax and semantics of focus-sensitive particles in German. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 19. 229–281. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1010653115493

Chierchia, Gennaro & Sally McConnell-Ginet. 1990. Meaning and grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Coppock, Elizabeth & David Beaver. 2014. A superlative argument for a minimal theory of definiteness. In Todd Snider, Sarah D’Antonio & Mia Weigand (eds.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 24. 177–196. Ithaca, NY: LSA and CLC. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v24i0.2432

Davidson, Donald. 1967. The logical form of action sentences. In Nicholas Resher (ed.), The logic of decision and action, 81–95. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

de Swart, Henriëtte. 2011. Mismatches and coercion. In Claudia Maienborn, Klaus von Heusinger & Paul Portner (eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning 1. 574–597. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110226614.574

Farkas, Donka F. & Henriëtte de Swart. 2003. The semantics of incorporation: From argument structure to discourse transparency. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

Fitzgibbons, Natalia, Yael Sharvit & Jon Gajewski. 2008. Plural superlatives and distributivity. In Tova Friedman & Satoshi Ito (eds.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 18. 302–318. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v18i0.2501

Gazdar, Gerald. 1979. Pragmatics: Implicature, presuppositions, and logical form. New York, NY: Academic Press.

Heim, Irene. 1999. Notes on superlatives. Ms. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. https://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/TI1MTlhZ/Superlative.pdf.

Herdan, Simona. 2008. A superlative theory of amount relatives. In Charles B. Chang & Hannah J. Haynie (eds.), Proceedings of the 26th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL 26), 234–242. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.

Hoekstra, Jarich. 2004. Alles is fleurich, ik bin it mei: On the comitative particle mei in Frisian and its counterparts in the other Germanic languages. In Leonie Cornips & Jenny Doetjes (eds.), Linguistics in the Netherlands 2004, 114–124. Amsterdam: Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/avt.21.14hoe

Horn, Laurence. 1969. A presuppositional analysis of only and even. In Robert Binnick, Alice Davison, Georgia Green & Jerry Morgan (eds.), Proceedings from the 5th Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS 5), 98–107. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago.

Jayez, Jacques. 2010. Projective meaning and attachment. In Maria Aloni, Harald Bastiaanse, Tikitu de Jager & Katrin Schulz (eds.), Logic, language and meaning. 17th Amsterdam Colloquium, Amsterdam, The Netherlands, December 16–18, 2009, revised selected papers, 325–334. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-14287-1_33

Kaufmann, Ingrid. 1995. Konzeptuelle Grundlagen semantischer Dekompositionsstrukturen: Die Kombinatorik lokaler Verben und prädikativer Komplemente. Tübingen: Niemeyer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110966077

Kennedy, Christopher. 2007. Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable adjectives. Linguistics & Philosophy 30. 1–45. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-006-9008-0

Kim, Jaegwon. 1976. Events as property exemplifications. In Myles Brand & Douglas Walton (eds.), Action theory. Proceedings of the Winnipeg conference on human action, 159–177. Dordrecht: Reidel. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9074-2_9

Lasersohn, Peter. 1998. Generalized distributivity operators. Linguistics and Philosophy 21. 273–292. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1005317815339

Lasersohn, Peter. 2011. Mass nouns and plurals. In Klaus von Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn & Paul Portner (eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning 2. 1131–1153. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110255072.1131

Maienborn, Claudia. 2003. Die logische Form von Kopula-Sätzen. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1524/9783050082271

Maienborn, Claudia. 2005. On the limits of the Davidsonian approach: The case of copula sentences. Theoretical Linguistics 31. 275–316. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/thli.2005.31.3.275

Maienborn, Claudia. 2015. Events and states. Ms. University of Tübingen (to appear in Handbook of event structure, ed. Robert Truswell, Oxford University Press). http://www.germ.uni-tuebingen.de/abteilungen/linguistik/personen/prof-dr-claudia-maienborn/publikationen.html.

Maienborn, Claudia & Johanna Herdtfelder. 2017. Eventive vs. stative causation: The case of German causal von-modifiers. Linguistics and Philosophy 40. 279–320. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-016-9201-8

Maienborn, Claudia & Martin Schäfer. 2011. Adverbs and adverbials. In Klaus von Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn & Paul Portner (eds.), Semantics:An international handbook of natural language meaning 2. 1390–1420. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110255072.1390

McNally, Louise & Henriëtte de Swart. 2015. Reference to and via properties: The view from Dutch. Linguistics and Philosophy 38. 315–362. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-015-9173-0

Moltmann, Friederike. 2004. The semantics of together. Natural Language Semantics 12. 289–318. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-004-6453-6

Moltmann, Friederike. 2009. Degree structure as trope structure: A trope-based analysis of positive and comparative adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy 32. 51–94. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-009-9054-5

Moltmann, Friederike. 2013. Abstract objects and the semantics of natural language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199608744.001.0001

Moltmann, Friederike. 2015. States versus tropes: Comments on Curt Anderson and Marcin Morzycki: ‘Degrees as kinds’. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 33. 829–841. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-015-9292-x

Parsons, Terence. 1990. Events in the Semantics of English: A Study in Subatomic Semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Potts, Christopher. 2005. The logic of conventional implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199273829.001.0001

Rapoport, Tova. 2014. Central coincidence: The preposition with. Faits de Langues 44. 159–173. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3726/431669_159

Schein, Barry. 2017. ‘And’: Conjunction reduction redux. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/10488.001.0001

Seiler, Hansjakob. 1974. The principle of concomitance: Instrumental, comitative, and collective. Foundations of Language 12. 215–247.

Simons, Mandy, Judith Tonhauser, David Beaver & Craige Roberts. 2010. What projects and why. In Nan Li & David Lutz (eds.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 20. 309–327. Ithaca, NY: LSA and CLC. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v20i0.2584

Stateva, Penka. 2005. Presuppositions in superlatives. Ms. Humboldt University Berlin. https://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/GU1Y2FkZ/Stateva-superlatives.pdf.

Strigin, Anatoli. 1995. Abductive inference during update: The German preposition mit. In Mandy Simons & Teresa Galloway (eds.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 5. 310–327. eLanguage: LSA Publications. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v5i0.2716

Sudhoff, Stefan. 2010. Focus particles in German: Syntax, prosody, and information structure. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/la.151

Tonhauser, Judith. 2012. Diagnosing (not-)at-issue content. In Elizabeth Bogal-Allbritten (ed.), Proceedings of Semantics of Under-represented Languages in the Americas (SULA) 6 and SULA-Bar, 239–254. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts, GLSA.

Tonhauser, Judith, David Beaver, Craige Roberts & Mandy Simons. 2013. Toward a taxonomy of projective content. Language 89. 66–109. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2013.0001

Zifonun, Gisela. 1996/1997. Ungewöhnliche Verwendungen von mit I/II. Deutsch als Fremdsprache 33/34. 218–222/20–25.

Zifonun, Gisela. 1999. Wenn mit alleine im Mittelfeld erscheint: Verbpartikeln und ihre Doppelgänger im Deutschen und Englischen. In Heide Wegener (ed.), Deutsch kontrastiv: Typologisch-vergleichende Untersuchungen zur deutschen Grammatik, 211–235. Tübingen: Stauffenburg.

Zifonun, Gisela, Ludger Hoffmann & Bruno Strecker. 1997. Grammatik der deutschen Sprache. 3 Bde. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.